provide us with an explicit procedure for making up our minds. It is
clearly left to the agent himself to decide what it is that he most wants and
to judge the comparative importance of his several ends.
At this point I introduce the notion of deliberative rationality following
an idea of Sidgwick’s. He characterizes a person’s future good on the
whole as what he would now desire and seek
if the consequences of all
the various courses of conduct open to him were, at the present point of
time, accurately foreseen by him and adequately realized in imagination.
An individual’s good is the hypothetical composition of impulsive forces
that results from deliberative reflection meeting certain conditions.
14
Ad-
justing Sidgwick’s notion to the choice of plans, we can say that the
rational plan for a person is the one (among those consistent with the
counting principles and other principles of rational choice once these are
established) which he would choose with deliberative rationality. It is the
plan that would be decided upon as the outcome of careful reflection in
which
the agent reviewed, in the light of all the relevant facts, what it
would be like to carry out these plans and thereby ascertained the course
of action that would best realize his more fundamental desires.
In this definition of deliberative rationality it is assumed that there are
no errors of calculation or reasoning, and that the facts are correctly
assessed. I suppose also that the agent is under no misconceptions as to
what he really wants. In most cases anyway,
when he achieves his aim, he
does not find that he no longer wants it and wishes that he had done
something else instead. Moreover, the agent’s knowledge of his situation
and the consequences of carrying out each plan is presumed to be accu-
rate and complete. No relevant circumstances are left out of account.
Thus the best plan for an individual is the one that he would adopt if he
possessed full information. It is the objectively rational plan for him and
determines his real good. As things are, of course,
our knowledge of
what will happen if we follow this or that plan is usually incomplete.
Often we do not know what is the rational plan for us; the most that we
can have is a reasonable belief as to where our good lies, and sometimes
we can only conjecture. But if the agent does the best that a rational
person can do with the information available to him, then the plan he
follows is a subjectively rational plan. His
choice may be an unhappy one,
but if so it is because his beliefs are understandably mistaken or his
knowledge insufficient, and not because he drew hasty and fallacious
inferences or was confused as to what he really wanted. In this case a
14. See
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: