rational individual is always to act so that he need never blame himself no
matter how his plans finally work out. Viewing himself as one continuing
being over time, he can say that at each moment of his life he has done
what the balance of reasons required, or at least permitted.
18
Therefore
any risks he assumes must be worthwhile, so that should the worst hap-
pen that he had any reason to foresee, he can still affirm that what he did
was above criticism. He does not regret his choice, at least not in the
sense that he later believes that at the time it would have been more
rational to have done otherwise. This principle will not certainly prevent
us from taking steps that lead to misadventure. Nothing can protect us
from the ambiguities and limitations of our knowledge, or guarantee that
we find the best alternative open to us. Acting with deliberative rationality
can only insure that our conduct is above reproach, and that we are
responsible to ourselves as one person over time. We should indeed be
surprised if someone said that he did not care about how he will view his
present actions later any more than he cares about the affairs of other
people (which is not much, let us suppose). One who rejects equally the
claims of his future self and the interests of others is not only irresponsi-
ble with respect to them but in regard to his own person as well. He does
not see himself as one enduring individual.
Now looked at in this way, the principle of responsibility to self resem-
bles a principle of right: the claims of the self at different times are to be
so adjusted that the self at each time can affirm the plan that has been and
is being followed. The person at one time, so to speak, must not be able to
complain about actions of the person at another time. This principle does
not, of course, exclude the willing endurance of hardship and suffering;
but it must be presently acceptable in view of the expected or achieved
good. From the standpoint of the original position the relevance of re-
sponsibility to self seems clear enough. Since the notion of deliberative
rationality applies there, it means that the parties cannot agree to a con-
ception of justice if the consequences of applying it may lead to self-re-
proach should the least happy possibilities be realized. They should strive
to be free from such regrets. And the principles of justice as fairness seem
to meet this requirement better than other conceptions, as we can see
from the earlier discussion of the strains of commitment (§29).
A final observation about goodness as rationality. It may be objected
that this conception implies that one should be continually planning and
18. For this and other points in this paragraph see Charles Fried,
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: