in part to encourage an ascetic way of life as a necessary requirement
for those intent on following theS.
u¯ fı¯ path. In 1106, he resumed his
teaching of Islamic law first at N¯ısh¯ap ¯ ur and then atT.u¯ s, where he
died in 1111. His return to the teaching of law saw the writing of
hismajor work on Islamic law, namely, The Choice Essentials of the
Principles ofReligion (al-Mustasf ¯ amin us.
u¯ l al-dı¯n).After thewriting
of the Ih. ya¯ ’, al-Ghaza¯ lı¯ wrote a number of important shorter works
which include among others the following: The Highest Goal in
Explaining the Beautiful Names of God (al-Maqs.
ad al-asna¯ fı¯ asma¯ ’
Alla¯h al-h. usna¯ ); The Decisive Criterion for Distinguishing Belief
from Unbelief (Faysal al-tafriqa bayn al-Islamwa al-zandaqa); The
Book of Forty (Kita¯b al-arba‘ı¯n), which sums up some main ideas
of the Ih. ya¯ ’; the two mystical works, The Alchemy of Happiness
(Kı¯mı¯a¯ -ye sa‘a¯dat) in Persian and The Niche of Lights (Mishka¯ t alanwa
¯ r); his autobiography, The Deliverer from Error (al-Munqidh
min al-d. ala¯ l); and his last work, Restraining the Commonality from
the Science of Kala¯m (Ilja¯m al-‘awa¯m ‘an ‘ilm al-kala¯m).
Al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı’s religious thought is multi-faceted and is expressed
in a variety of contexts. One way to approach it is to discuss it first
in terms of the relation of his Ash‘arite theology to philosophy and
then in relation to his mysticism.
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı 141
ghaza ̄ lı ̄ and the ash‘arites
The work in which al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı expresses his Ash‘arite theology in
detail is the Moderation in Belief. It is significant that he expressed
his high regard for this work long after he had become aS.
u¯ fı¯, in The
Book of Forty (written after the Ih. ya¯ ’), in which he proclaims that
the Moderation in Belief contains the essentials of the science of the
theologians, in effect, the Ash‘arite theologians (al-mutakallim¯ın).
He then adds that it goes deeper than the Ash‘arite works of kala¯m
in ascertaining the truth and “is closer to knocking at the door of
gnosis” (abwa¯b al-ma‘rifa) than the “official discourse” (al-kala¯m
al-rasm¯ı) encountered in their books.5 It is significant that he did
not regard it as one of the “official” Ash‘arite works and that he held
it to be superior to such works in ascertaining what is true.
The cornerstone of Ash‘arite theology is its doctrine of the divine
attributes. Al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı endorses and expands on this doctrine. For
the Ash‘arites, the divine attributes of life, knowledge, will, power,
speech, hearing, and seeing are co-eternal with the divine essence
and intimately related to it, but are not identical with it. They are
attributes “additional” (za¯ ’ida) to the divine essence. This point is
quite basic, particularly for understanding al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı’s rejection and
condemnation of the philosophical doctrine of an eternal world. For
if these attributes are identical with the divine essence, then the
divine act would be an essential act, an act which proceeds as the
necessary consequence of the very essence or nature of God. Now for
Avicenna, with whom al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı is contending, God is the supreme
essential cause for all the existents that successively emanate from
him, the totality of which is the world. According to Avicenna, the
priority of the essential cause to its effect is ontological, not temporal.
The essential cause coexists with its effect. Hence, for Avicenna,
the world as the necessitated effect of the eternal essential cause is
necessarily eternal.
This consequence meant for al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı the negation of the divine
attribute of will. To be sure, for al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı, whatever the divine eternal
will chooses and decrees must come about. In this sense the
existence of what it decrees is necessary. It is not, however, necessitated
by the divine essence. Not being identical with the divine
essence, the eternal will does not have to decree the creation of the
world. It does so “freely,” so to speak, by an eternal voluntary act.
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
142 michael e. marmura
According to al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı, by this act it decrees the world’s creation
out of nothing (ex nihilo) at a finite moment in time in the past from
the present.
Whatever the divine will decrees comes about through the
attribute of divine power. This brings us to the relation of the divine
attributes of life, knowledge,will, and power to each other. These are
conditionally related. There can be no knowledge without life, no
will without knowledge, and no power without will. Each, that is
life, knowledge, will, and power, is respectively a necessary condition
for the other. This does not, however, mean that they “cause”
each other. They are eternal coexisting uncaused attributes. Moreover,
the eternal will decrees that all created existents and events
follow a uniform course. Al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı refers to this uniform course
as ijra¯ ’ al-‘a¯da, God’s ordaining things to flow according to a habitual
course. But this habitual course is not in itself necessary. It can
be disrupted without contradiction. The eternal will that decrees
this uniform, habitual course decrees also its disruptions at certain
moments of history. These disruptions are the miracles that God
creates on behalf of his prophets and holy men.
The divine attribute of power is the sole cause of all created things
and events.6 It is also pervasive. By this al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı means that divine
power is one, not divisible into many powers, and is the cause of each
and every created existent and event. Our world consists of bodies,
composed of indivisible atoms and accidents that inhere in them.
The atoms, the accidents, the bodies they compose, and all sequences
of events are the direct creation of this pervasive divine power. The
uniform course of events constitutes an order which includes what
we habitually regard as causes and effects. But while these behave as
though they are real causes and effects, in fact they are not. They are
concomitant events that are not necessarily connected with each
other and are causally connected only with the one cause, divine
power. This brings us to what is meant by saying that this theology
is occasionalist. Events habitually regarded as causes are merely the
occasions for divine, direct, real causal action. They follow an order
that parallels the order (in all its details) of what Avicenna regards
as real causes and effects, so that normally one can draw “demonstrative”
inferences from the chains of occasionalist/habitual causes
and effects.7
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı 143
At the heart of Ash‘arite occasionalism is their doctrine of “acquisition”
(kasb). Human acts, like all other events, are the direct creation
of divine power. This power creates in us power we experience
as the cause of our deliberate actions. But just as the events we normally
regard as causes and effects are concomitants, created by divine
power, so are those acts we normally believe to be our deliberate
acts. They are acts concomitant with the events we normally regard
as the “effects” of this power. These “effects,” however, are not of
our doing. They are created for us by divine power. In other words,
the power created in us has no causal efficacy. Whatever we believe
to have been “acquired” by our own power is in reality acquired on
our behalf by divine power. Al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı insists that the created power
in us exists only with the acquisition the divine power creates for
us. Created power does not temporally precede the human act. It and
the act are created simultaneously. Moreover, divine power cannot
enact the impossible. It cannot enact in us created power without
first creating in us respectively life, knowledge, and will. Each of
these, however, is the direct creation of divine power.
If this then is the case, how can we differentiate our spasmodic
movements from those movements we normally regard as deliberate?
The classic Ash‘arite answer, which al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı endorses, is that
in the case of the spasmodic movement, such a movement is created
without the created power, whereas what is normally regarded as the
deliberate movement is created with it. This is how they differ. We
ourselves experience this difference. This, however, does not resolve
the question of how this theory can account for human moral responsibility,
premised on the doctrine of the freedom of the human will.
Al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı is hardly unaware of this problem. But he supports this
theory of acquisition, suggesting that a resolution of its difficulties
is attained when, through mystical vision, its place in the cosmic
scheme of things is understood.
the incoherence
Al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı’s Ash‘arite occasionalist perspective given in the Moderation
in Belief is reiterated in different contexts in the Ih. ya¯ ’, as
we shall point out. This perspective forms the background of the
Incoherence and helps us better understand some of its arguments.
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
144 michael e. marmura
Now it is true that al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı regarded the Incoherence as a work
of refutation and did not intend it to be an exposition of Ash‘arite theology.
He thus declares quite plainly that he is not writing the book
from any one specific doctrinal position (Incoherence, 7). Moreover,
on two notable occasions he adopts some of the views of his philosopher
opponents to show that even in terms of their own theories, the
literal scriptural assertions they deem impossible are in fact possible.
In this he is quite consistent with his declaration that the primary
intention of the Incoherence is to refute, not to build up doctrine.
Al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı, however, in one of his later works,8 declared the Incoherence
as belonging to the genre of kala¯m works – this not inconsistently.
For he held the main task of Ash‘arite kala¯m to be the
defence of what he conceived to be Islamic Sunn¯ı doctrine. The Incoherence
constitutes such a defence, even though it does not set out
to formulate a doctrine (Incoherence, 7). At the same time, there
are many assertions and hidden premises in this work that when
extracted convey a specific theological view, namely, the Ash‘arite.
As we will indicate, an Ash‘arite assertion is introduced as part of
al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı’s method of refuting. Hence when the chief critic of this
work, Averroes, in his Incoherence of the Incoherence (Taha¯ fut altaha
¯ fut) repeatedly refers to al-Ghaza¯ lı¯’s stance in the Incoherence
as Ash‘arite, he is to a good extent justified. But before turning to the
Ash‘arite base that underlies much of the arguments of the Incoherence,
a brief word about this work is necessary.
In the Incoherence, al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı singled out for criticism the
philosophies of al-F ¯ar¯ab¯ı and Avicenna. These two, he holds, are the
best exponents of the philosophy of Aristotle. Here, however, we
have to be reminded that while these two were Aristotelians, they
were also Neoplatonists, each constructing an emanative scheme
that has its own peculiarities. Their respective emanative schemes,
though similar, are not identical. Moreover, their theories of the
soul and eschatologies are also not identical. Al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı’s critique
has as its more direct object the philosophy of Avicenna. Nonetheless,
many of these criticisms apply to aspects of al-F ¯ar¯ab¯ı’s thought.
In the Incoherence al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı sometimes refers specifically to Avicenna,
but in general he simply refers to his opponents as “the
philosophers.”
The Incoherence is aimed at refuting those philosophical ideas
deemed by al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı to contravene Islamic religious belief. It thus
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı 145
addresses itself to twenty philosophical theories, three of which it
holds to be utterly opposed to Islamic religious belief, those upholding
them to be infidels, to be groupedwith heretical innovations that
some Islamic sect or another had held. The three theories he condemns
as utterly opposed to Islamic teaching are the theory of a preeternal
world, the theory (specifically Avicennian) that God knows
only the universal aspects of terrestrial particulars, and Avicenna’s
doctrine of the immortal, immaterial soul that denies bodily resurrection.
To refute such theories, all that al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı needs to show
is that contrary to the philosophers’ claims, these theories have not
been demonstrated. He certainly endeavors to do this, but he also
argues that some of them are self-contradictory.
causality
The Ash‘arism of the Incoherence is best seen in discussions where
the concept of causality is involved. The First Discussion is devoted
to the question of the world’s origin, and consists of a debate of
four philosophical proofs for the world’s pre-eternity. The debate
of the first proof is the longest. The philosophers’ proof, which al-
Ghaz¯ al¯ı regards as their strongest, is premised on the theory of divine
essential causality. According to the philosophers, a world created
in time would mean the delay of the effect of a necessitating cause
(namely God) when there can be no impediment or any other reason
to account for such a delay. After presenting the philosophers’ argument
in its most forceful way, al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı begins his refutation by
asking whether the philosophers can demonstrate the impossibility
of the contradictory of its conclusion, namely, the Ash‘arite doctrine
that the world is created at that moment of time which the eternal
divine will has chosen and decreed for its creation (Incoherence,
17). He argues that they can do this neither syllogistically nor by an
appeal to what is self-evidently necessary. If the denial of the conclusion
cannot be proven to be untrue, then its premise that the divine
essential cause necessitates its effect remains unproven. At the conclusion
of this multi-faceted debate, he refers to the philosophers’
theory that the cause for the occurrence of temporal events is the
circular movement of the celestial spheres. He denies this, affirming
the Ash‘arite view that all temporal events are “the initial inventions”
of God (mukhtara‘a li-al-La¯hi ibtida¯ ‘an; Incoherence, 30).
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
146 michael e. marmura
In the Third Discussion, al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı discusses the use of the term
“agent.” Agency belongs only to a living, willing, knowing being.
When the opponent appeals to correct Arabic usage, as, for example,
when it is said that fire kills, al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı insists that this is merely
metaphorical usage: fire as such in reality has no action (Incoherence,
58–9) – a point repeated in the Seventeenth Discussion.
While the Seventeenth Discussion is devoted to causality, its real
purpose is to show that some of the miracles, reported in the Qur‘ ¯an
and the prophetic traditions but considered by the philosophers as
impossible, are possible.9 Al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı begins the discussion with the
Ash‘arite declaration: “the connection between what is habitually
believed to be a cause and what is habitually believed to be the effect
is not necessary for us.” With any two things, he continues, that
are not identical, where neither the affirmation or negation of the
one entails the affirmation or negation of the other, the existence or
nonexistence of the one does not entail the existence or nonexistence
of the other. He then gives as examples, “the quenching of thirst and
drinking, satiety and eating, light and the appearance of the sun,
death and decapitation.” The connection of these and other such
observable things is due to the prior decree of God, who creates them
side by side. The connections between them are not in themselves
necessary and they are hence capable of separation. It is thus within
divine power, for example, to create death without decapitation and
to continue life after decapitation (Incoherence, 166).
Al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı then takes his well-known example of the contact of
a piece of cotton with fire. What we see is the occurrence of the
burning of cotton at the point of contact with the fire.We do not see
its being burnt by the fire. What we witness are two concomitant
events. He then asserts that the one who enacts the burning by creating
blackness in the cotton, producing separation in its parts, and
rendering it cinder and ashes, is God, either directly or through the
mediation of his angels (Incoherence, 167). (We will be turning to
the question of what al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı means by angelic mediation when
discussing aspects of the Ih. ya¯ ’.)
As the discussion of causality proceeds, al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı puts in the
mouth of his opponents a major objection. From the denial of necessary
causal connection in natural events, they argue, repugnant
impossibilities will ensue. There will be no order in the world.
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı 147
All occurrences would be sheer possibilities whose contraries can
equally occur. A man, for example, will be confronted by wild beasts
and raging fires but will not see them because God has not created
sight for him. All kinds of similar absurdities will then follow
(Incoherence, 169–70). To this al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı replies that if things
whose existence is possible are such that there cannot be created for
an individual knowledge of their nonexistence, the impossibilities
the opponents mention would follow. These things they mention,
however, he goes on, are mere possibilities that may or may not
occur. God, al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı then asserts, creates in us the knowledge that
he did not enact these possibilities. (Implicit in this answer is al-
Ghaza¯ lı¯’s concept of ijra¯ ’ al-‘a¯da, God’s ordaining events to proceed
along a uniform, orderly, habitual course.) As such, the philosophers’
objection amounts to nothing more than sheer vilification
(Incoherence, 170).
Still, to avoid being subject to such vilification, al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı proposes
another causal theory (Incoherence, 171–4). He will concede
that when fire touches two similar pieces of cotton it will burn both.
A measure of causal efficacy is thus allowed in things. But it is
allowed only if the divine act remains voluntary, not necessitated
by his essence, and divine power is such that it can intervene in
nature to allow the miracle. Thus, for example, a prophet placed in
a fiery furnace may be miraculously saved, either by God’s changing
the character of the fire or by creating a cause that impedes its action.
Now al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı tells us that both theories, the Ash‘arite, and the
modified philosophical theory that allows a measure of causal efficacy
in natural things, are possible. But in what sense are both possible?
As they are mutually exclusive, one denying causal efficacy in
things, one allowing it, they cannot be compossible. What al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı
probably means is that either theory, independently of the other, is
internally consistent and that each allows the possibility of those
miracles deemed impossible by the philosophers. This parallels his
argument in the Twentieth Discussion where he concedes the possibility
of the human soul’s being immaterial and proceeds to argue
that even if this is granted, bodily resurrection, denied by Avicenna,
is still possible. In the Moderation in Belief, where al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı reaffirms
the Ash‘arite doctrine of a material soul, he refers us back to
the Incoherence, saying:
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
148 michael e. marmura
We have treated this problem in detail in the Incoherence adopting in refuting
the philosophers’ doctrine the view that affirms the immortality of the
soul – which according to them has no position in space – and that allows
the resumption of its management of the body, regardless of whether or
not such a body is the same as the original human body. This, however,
is a consequence [we made logically incumbent on them to accept] that
does not agree with what we believe. For that book was written for the
purpose of refuting their doctrine, not for the purpose of establishing true
doctrine.10
Turning back to the second causal argument, we find no reaffirmation
of it in theModeration in Belief, nor in the Ih. ya¯ ’ and subsequent
writings. All the indications are that it was introduced in the Incoherence
for the sake of argument, to show that even if one concedes a
measure of causal efficacy in things, one can still accept themiracles
rejected by the philosophers.
The Moderation in Belief affirms the Ash‘arite occasionalist position
forcefully and unequivocally. It reaffirms it by a detailed refutation
of the doctrine of generation (al-tawallud) espoused by the
Mu‘tazilite school of kala¯m, a doctrine al-Ghaza¯ lı¯ in the Incoherence
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |