All dogs are animals
All dachshunds are animals
necessity (5a_) obtains in the two premises and necessity (5a__) obtains
in the conclusion, while necessity (5b) obtains in the act of inferring
the conclusion from the premises. Put another way, necessity (5a_)
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Avicenna 117
refers to the necessity that a cause possesses (in this case, the causes
are the premises) and necessity (5a__) refers to the necessity that a
cause produces in its effect (in this case, the effect is the conclusion).
Necessity (5b), by contrast, refers to the necessity that obtains in the
cause’s act of causing or producing its effect: given the (5a_) necessity
possessed by the cause (or the premises), the (5a__) necessity of the
effect (or conclusion) follows by (5b) necessity. In a way, (5a_) and
(5a__) both refer to necessity, whereas (5b) refers to necessitation.
At the conceptual level, as opposed to the lexical or terminological
level, Metaphysics, V.5 provided Avicenna with most of the
raw material he needed to fashion his distinction between (A) “[the]
necessary of existence in itself” (wa¯ jib al-wuju¯ d bi-dha¯ tihi) and (B)
“[the] necessary of existence through another” (wa¯ jib al-wuju¯ d bighayrihi).
But before explaining how and why Avicenna appropriated
this material I shall first describe the terminological sources
of Avicenna’s distinction, since, as mentioned above, the term used
in the Arabic translation of the Metaphysics for anankaion (“necessary”)
is mud.t.
arr and notwa¯ jib as in Avicenna’s distinction. Instead,
the most likely terminological source of Avicenna’s distinction is De
Interpretatione, XII–XIII, the chapters of the De Interpretatione in
which Aristotle is concerned with the nature of modality. That is to
say, Aristotle wants to determine as precisely as he can what it is
we mean when we say that a proposition is necessary, possible, or
impossible; or, put another way, what it is we mean when we say that
it is necessary, possible or impossible that predicate P (e.g., “dog”)
holds of subject S (“dachshund”). Why should Aristotle want to do
this? The reason is that in the next treatise of the Organon Aristotle
is very concerned with the implications of necessity. In the Prior
Analytics, Aristotle begins by investigating the structure and behavior
of assertoric syllogisms, but quickly turns to the structure and
behavior of modal syllogisms, i.e., those syllogisms whose premises
and conclusion contain modal qualifiers such as “necessarily” or
“necessary [that].”
In the course of rendering De Interpretatione, XII–XIII into Arabic
the translator made two important lexical moves. First, he
started to use the more existential Arabic root w-j-d (as in wuju¯ d,
“existence”), instead of the more copulative k-w-n, to translate
Aristotle’s copulative uses of the Greek verb einai, “to be.” The second
move was using w-j-b instead of d.
-r-r to translate anankaion,
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
118 robert wisnovsky
“necessary.” In my opinion the move from k-w-n to w-j-d in
translating einai is evidence that the translator worried about
Aristotle’s uncertainty over whether possibility is one-sided (i.e.,
opposed in a contradictory way only to impossibility) or twosided
(opposed in a contradictory way to impossibility and to
necessity); and that the greater existential weight conveyed by
the root w-j-d (in contrast to the more copulative k-w-n) helped
the translator come down on the side of two-sided possibility.
This is because w-j-d appeared to be usable both as a copula
in propositions, where the logical mode mumkin – “possible
[that S is P]” – is the contradictory of the mode mumtani‘ –
“impossible [that S is P]”; and as an existential signifier in descriptions
of real beings, in which the existential state wa¯ jib – “necessary
[of existence],” here meaning “a being which is uncaused” – is
the contradictory of the existential state mumkin – “possible [of
existence],” here meaning “a being which is caused.” In other words,
the translator chose w-j-d because that Arabic root better ensured
that mumkin was able to performthe dual role that Aristotle seemed
to expect of dunaton, as meaning both “possible” (i.e., the contradictory
of “impossible”) and “contingent” (i.e., the contradictory of
“necessary”).
As for the translator’s move from d.
-r-r to w-j-b in translating
anankaion, my sense is that whereas d.
-r-r could have conveyed
the (5a_) and (5a__) senses of necessity – that is, the necessity possessed,
respectively, by the premises and by the conclusion in a
valid syllogism – only w-j-b could also have conveyed the (5b) sense
of inferential necessity – of necessitation, that is. This is because
the Arabic verb wajaba/yajibu was the standard term one turned
to when one wanted to say that a conclusion “follows necessarily
from” its premises.
The result of these two shifts in translation patterns is that
Avicenna was provided with an Aristotelian text in which the
phrases wa¯ jib al-wuju¯ d (“necessary of existence”) and mumkin
al-wuju¯ d (“possible of existence”) were both prominently used.
However, the last remaining pieces of raw material – the qualifiers
bi-dha¯ tihi (“in itself”) and bi-ghayrihi (“through another”) – though
they appeared in al-F ¯ar¯ab¯ı’s Commentary on the “De Interpretatione,”
seem in fact to have come to Avicenna from kala¯m
treatments of the problem of God’s attributes, a topic I shall turn
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Avicenna 119
to now, in my discussion of the two main problems that Avicenna
was trying to solve by coming up with his new distinction.
Objectives
The first problem dealtwith byAvicenna’s new distinction was: how
is a duality – conceptual, if not real – in God to be avoided? Like the
Mu‘tazil¯ıs, the Neoplatonists had insisted on a strict understanding
of God’s oneness – as simplicity, and not merely as uniqueness.
Yet the efforts by commentators of the Ammonian synthesis to reconcile
Plato’s and Aristotle’s theories of God’s causality ultimately
produced a God who was a composite of efficient causality and final
causality. God as efficient cause was either the Demiurge of Plato’s
Timaeus, who creates the world out of matter but in view of the
transcendent Forms; or it was the Neoplatonists’ One, who is the
original source of the downward procession (proo¨dos) of existence (to
einai) to each thing in the universe. God as final cause was either the
Unmoved Mover of Aristotle’s Physics and Metaphysics, who serves
as a goal, impelling the eternal circular motion of the heavens; or it
was the Neoplatonists’ Good, who is the ultimate destination of the
upward reversion (epistrophˆe) of each thing toward the well-being (to
eu einai) that is peculiar to its species. For Avicenna it was simply
not good enough to assert, as some Greek Neoplatonists had, that in
God no real duality is entailed by his being both an efficient cause
and a final cause, and that what appears to us to be a conceptual
duality between God’s two causal roles is a reflection of the fact that
human minds are just too feeble to apprehend the real identity of
efficient and final causality in God. Avicenna’s discomfort with this
dodge may have been exacerbated by the fact that the Ammonians
had actually papered over a more fundamental disjunction. After all,
God’s final causality and his efficient causality not only served as
explanations of the ways inwhich God causes the universe, they also
expressed in what were then seen as scientific terms the two basic
qualities that God should possess: on the one hand being utterly separate
from and transcendent of the world (a quality more compatible
with God’s being a final cause), and on the other hand being creatively
involved with and productive of the world (a quality more
compatible with God’s being an efficient cause).
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
120 robert wisnovsky
Avicenna was able to take a fresh approach to this first challenge
because by his time the Ammonian synthesis had pretty much run
out of steam. By this I mean that Avicenna, born and raised and
educated at the periphery of the Islamic world, had no professional
teachers to instill in him the hermeneutical commitments of the
Ammonian synthesis. As a result Avicenna felt under little obligation
to adhere to the original interpretive premises that had caused
earlier Ammonians to cut philosophical corners in order to harmonize
Plato and Aristotle – or more specifically, in order to advance
the Ammonian project of folding the greater harmony into the lesser
harmony. These hermeneutical commitments were still operative
in works as recent as those of Avicenna’s predecessor al-F ¯ar¯ab¯ı, who
had received his philosophical education in the Aristotelian school
in metropolitan Baghdad.25
Because of Avicenna’s peripheral education – because he was
almost entirely self-educated, in fact – he inherited the old set of
problems created by the Ammonian synthesis yet without any motivation
to keep him working within its rules; without any motivation,
that is, to keep him from simply discarding or moving beyond
those old Ammonian problems. True, some of the problems Avicenna
inherited had already been solved within the context of the
Ammonian synthesis, a prominent example being the question of
the soul’s relationship to the body, as I discussed earlier. But the
conceptual duality entailed by God’s being both a final and efficient
cause remained an unsolved problem.26
The way that Avicenna side-stepped the Ammonians’ commitment
to God’s troublesome combination of efficient and final causality
was to propose a new formula to describe God: “[the] necessary of
existence in itself.” Avicenna’s new formula enjoyed the enormous
advantage of being syntactically amphibolous. That is to say, “necessary
of existence in itself” can be construed both intransitively and
transitively, and therefore can be understood as referring to a being
who is transcendent of the world and productive of it at the same
time. Understood intransitively, Avicenna’s God satisfies the criteria
of Aristotle’s type (4) necessity, when type (4) necessity is viewed
as the grab-bag of intransitive divine qualities, such as simplicity,
immutability, and eternality; as well as the criteria ofAristotle’s type
(5a_) necessity, that is, the necessity with which a predicate holds
of a subject, when that subject-predicate combination is viewed in
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Avicenna 121
itself, as a stand-alone proposition. Understood transitively,
Avicenna’s God also satisfies the criteria of Aristotle’s type (4) necessity,
when type (4) necessity is understood as the basic necessity from
which all other necessities derive; as well as the criteria of Aristotle’s
type (5a_) necessity, the necessity with which a predicate holds of a
subject, when that subject-predicate combination is viewed not as
a stand-alone proposition but rather as a premise in a syllogism –
when it is viewed, in other words, as productive of the necessity of a
conclusion. And in this latter, transitive case, the effect which is produced
corresponds to Aristotle’s (5a__) necessity, the necessity that a
conclusion possesses but which is produced by the (5a_) necessity of
the premises. This effect of the transitive necessary of existence in
itself is the necessary of existence through another.
The second problem that Avicenna’s new distinction helped to
solve was: how is one to distinguish between God and other eternal
things? The elaborate pleromas constructed by various Neoplatonic
thinkers – cosmologies that reached their peak (or depth) of complexity
in the works of Proclus – cried out for a simple and basic
way to differentiate the First Cause from the monads and henads
and gods and intellects all crowding round it. Amongst the Sunn¯ı
mutakallimu¯ n, the problemwas expressed in terms of finding a way
to distinguish between God’s self (dha¯ t) and God’s eternal attributes
(s.
if ¯ at), such as his knowledge (‘ilm), power (qudra), and life (h.
aya¯ t).
The Sunn¯ıs had insisted on the reality, eternality, and distinctiveness
of the divine attributes. This was in contrast to the Mu‘tazil¯ıs,
who refused to grant the divine attributes any separate reality, arguing
that while the attributes can be distinguished from each other
and fromGod’s self (dha¯ t) at a purely conceptual level, in reality they
are all identical to God’s self. By the Mu‘tazil¯ıs’ reckoning, a cluster
of eternal, real, and distinct attributes violated Islam’s cardinal tenet
of God’s oneness (tawh. ¯ıd). If, for example, the divine attributes were
really distinct from God’s self, then there would be a plurality of eternal
entities, and God’s oneness, understood as his uniqueness, would
be infringed upon. If, on the other hand, the divine attributes were
not really separate from God’s self but were instead containedwithin
it, yet were still distinct enough to be really differentiated one from
the other, then God’s oneness, understood as his simplicity, would
be violated. Solving this second problem – finding a watertight way
to distinguish between God and other eternal things – was clearly in
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
122 robert wisnovsky
Avicenna’s mind when he composed his first philosophical treatise,
which I shall discuss in the next subsection.
Evolution
How did the various ways in which Avicenna articulated, justified,
and employed his distinction between (A) “necessary of existence
in itself,” and (B) “necessary of existence through another” – (C)
“possible of existence in itself,” evolve over his career? Is there as
much evidence of inconsistency and uncertainty as there was with
his distinction between essence and existence? The answer to the
second question is no: the ways Avicenna expressed, argued for and
employed his distinction between (A) and (B–C) are more coherent –
and hence his overall theory is less underdetermined – than the
ways in which he expressed, argued for, and employed his distinction
between essence and existence. Nevertheless, in answer to the
first question, two trends in his approach to the distinction between
(A) and (B–C) can be detected, trends that are clearly distinct at the
beginning of his career but which became increasingly interwoven
as his career progressed.
Avicenna’s distinction between (A) and (B–C) first appears in his
earliest philosophical summa, the Philosophy for ‘Aru¯ d. ı¯ (al-H. ikma
al-‘Aru¯ d. iyya), dating from around 1001, when Avicenna was just
twenty-one years old, and commissioned by a neighbor of his in
Bukh¯ar¯a. In that work, most of which remains unedited, Avicenna
introduces two ways of distinguishing between different types of
necessary existence: necessary of existence in itself as opposed to
necessary of existence through another; and necessary of existence
at all times as opposed to necessary of existence at some time and
not at other times. Avicenna plumps for the former way of distinguishing
between different types of necessary existence, because he
thinks the “in itself” vs. “through another” method will better warrant
an identification of the necessary of existence in itself with the
uncaused and the necessary of existence through another with the
caused than the “at all times” vs. “at some times and not other
times” method will.
The reason why Avicenna makes this choice is that he has inmind
the second major challenge discussed in the previous subsection,
namely, finding some way to distinguish between God and other
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Avicenna 123
eternal things, or, put another way, finding some way to distinguish
between something eternal which is uncaused and something eternal
which is caused. In Avicenna’s case, the eternal things that are
caused consist in the celestial spheres, the celestial souls that motivate
them, and the celestial intellects whose serene (and motionless)
eternality serves as the object of the celestial souls’ desire. For Neoplatonists
such as Proclus, as mentioned above, this category (eternal
but caused) comprises the full complement of gods, henads, monads,
and intellects. For the Sunnı¯ mutakallimu¯ n, “eternal but caused”
(or better, “eternal but not uncaused”) applies to the eternal divine
attributes, each of whose individual reality was distinct enough from
God’s self to raise warning flags about the consequences of creating a
pleroma of eternal and divine – though not causally self-sufficient –
things. Since the problem facing Avicenna revolved around differentiating
between eternal things, the “necessary at all times” vs.
“necessary sometimes” distinction was of little help, since the qualifier
“at all times” covers all eternal things, instead of distinguishing
between them.
By contrast, the “in itself” vs. “through another” method of distinguishing
between types of necessary existence was better equipped
to ensure the distinctness of God, the only uncaused being, from
all caused beings, be they eternal (such as the celestial spheres,
souls, or intellects) or temporally originated (such as you or I). In
the Philosophy for ‘Aru¯ d. ı¯ Avicenna justified his identification of
the necessary of existence in itself with the uncaused, and his identification
of the necessary of existence through another with the
caused, by asserting that the necessary of existence in itself, unlike
the necessary of existence through another, is not divisible into
two modes or states (h.
a¯ latayni). His reasoning was that whatever
is divisible into two modes or states will be a composite of those
two modes or states, and since every composite requires a composer
and is therefore caused, everything divisible into two modes
or states will be caused. By contrast, everything simple – here meaning
not even conceptually divisible – will be uncaused. But what
do the two modes or states refer to? Here Avicenna is unclear. The
two modes or states could refer to (1) the fact that a being which
is necessary of existence through another is also possible of existence
in itself, and will therefore be divisible into those two modes
of being (i.e., B and C). This is in contrast to a being which is
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
124 robert wisnovsky
necessary of existence in itself, which is only ever conceivable as
being necessary of existence in itself (i.e., only A), and hence is indivisible
into two modes of being. The problemwith this interpretation
is that Avicenna also asserts in this passage that whatever is subject
to change will possess neither mode in itself. But whatever is necessary
of existence through another and possible of existence through
itself does possess one of those two states in itself, namely, being
possible of existence.
Alternatively, the two modes or states could refer to (2) the state
of nonexistence and existence which obtain in the necessary of existence
through another, with nonexistence obtaining before the necessary
of existence through another comes into being and also after it
passes away, and existence obtainingwhile the necessary of existence
through another actually exists. The problem with this interpretation
is that it cannot account for beings which are caused but also
eternal, since they are never nonexistent and hence never divisible
into the states of nonexistence and existence. A final alternative is
that the two modes or states into which the necessary of existence
through another is divisible refer to (3) the state of potentiality (or
imperfection) and the state of actuality (or perfection) that simultaneously
obtain in something subject to change. After all, a log is
conceptually divisible into two states: actuality (i.e., as actual wood)
and potentiality (i.e., as potential fire). This interpretation works
a bit better than interpretation (2) in accounting for eternal things
which are caused, for even though the celestial spheres are never
nonexistent, they are subject to change and therefore exhibit potentiality
(they move in an eternal circular motion); and even though
the celestial souls are never nonexistent, they are perfectible (they
yearn to be assimilated into the celestial intellects that are paired
with them). Nevertheless, interpretation (3) still fails to account for
the celestial intellects, which by Avicenna’s reckoning are all fully
actual and perfect, uninfected by any potentiality or imperfection
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |