whatsoever. The result is that interpretation (3) will fail to account
for all eternal but caused things.
Perhaps because of his frustration at not coming up with a satisfactory
way to justify his assertion that the necessary of existence
through another will be divisible into two modes or states
and therefore be caused, Avicenna changed tack entirely in his next
work, the Origin and Destination (al-Mabda’ wa-al-ma‘a¯d), written
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Avicenna 125
around 1013, when he was 33 or so. In contrast to the Philosophy for
‘Aru¯ d. ı¯, where Avicenna begins with a distinction between the necessary
of existence in itself and the necessary of existence through
another, and then moves to identify the necessary of existence
through another with the possible of existence in itself, Avicenna
starts his discussion in the Origin and Destination by distinguishing
the necessary of existence and the possible of existence, and only
after doing that moves on to identify the possible of existence with
the necessary of existence through another. What advantage did this
new approach give to Avicenna? How did it provide a way for him
to unblock the logjam that had frustrated him in the Philosophy for
‘Aru¯ d. ı¯?
By 1013, when he wrote the Origin and Destination, Avicenna
apparently felt that the distinction between the necessary of existence
and the possible of existence was sufficiently intuitive that he
could simply assert that the necessary of existence is by definition
that whose nonexistence is inconceivable, whereas the possible of
existence is by definition that whose nonexistence is conceivable.
(The impossible of existence, which we need not worry about too
much, is by definition that whose existence is inconceivable.) Once
he had laid out this assumed basis for the distinction, Avicenna then
claimed that we can conceive of the existence of something which is
possible of existence only in the context of a relation which that possibly
existent thing has, namely, the relation it has with its cause. It
is in virtue of this relation with its cause, Avicenna asserts, that the
possible of existence is also necessary of existence through another;
in itself – that is, conceived of in isolation from its relation to its
cause – it remains only possible of existence.
The advantage of the Origin and Destination’s approach to the
distinction is that in it Avicenna felt under no obligation to argue
that the causedness of the necessary of existence through another
results from its being composed of two modes or states, and this
in turn freed him from having to explain precisely what those two
modes or statesmight be. In the Origin and Destination, the causedness
of the possible of existence stems from its relation to its cause,
a relation whose nonexistence is inconceivable once we posit the
actual existence of something which is possible of existence. On the
other hand, the Origin and Destination’s approach could be faulted
for assuming too much – for assuming, that is, that everyone would
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
126 robert wisnovsky
find its ontological or definitional approach to the distinction to be
so intuitive that the distinction could now bear all the cosmological
weight that would be piled on top of it. After all, the distinction did
serve as the axis of Avicenna’s analysis of all reality in the universe.
In his middle period, the period when he wrote his greatest philosophical
work, The Healing, Avicenna continued to appeal to the
Origin and Destination’s definitional, assumed basis for his distinction.
But in the Metaphysics of The Healing, a crucial thought seems
to have occurred to him. As discussed above, Avicenna argues in
Metaphysics 1.5 that thing and existent – and by implication, essence
and existence – are extensionally identical but intensionally distinct.
Every thing will also be an existent, and every existent will also be a
thing, but to be a thing and to be an existent have different meanings.
In the very next chapter, Metaphysics 1.6, Avicenna distinguishes
between the necessary of existence, the possible of existence, and
the impossible of existence, following the definitional approach he
took in the Origin and Destination, although the phrases he uses are
slightly different. Slightly later on in this chapter, Avicenna introduces
the term ma¯hiyya, essence, into the discussion: that whose
essence is insufficient for it to exist will be caused, whereas that
whose essence is sufficient for it to exist will be uncaused. The new
distinction Avicenna draws here is less important for what it lays
out than for what it represents, because it is here, I believe, that
it occurs to Avicenna to use his essence vs. existence distinction
to provide the conceptual divisibility – and hence compositeness,
and hence causedness – of any being that is necessary of existence
through another and possible of existence in itself, a conceptual divisibility
that he had groped for unsuccessfully twenty-five years earlier
in the Philosophy for ‘Aru¯ d. ı¯.
In fact it is only toward the end of the Metaphysics of The Healing
that Avicenna actually appeals to the essence vs. existence distinction
in this way. In Metaphysics 8.4, a chapter devoted to proving
God’s existence as well as his uniqueness, Avicenna argues that God
is the only being that is necessary of existence in itself because only
God is not divisible into essence and existence, unlike all other
beings, which are composites of essence and existence, and hence
caused, and hence merely necessary of existence through another
and possible of existence in themselves. In God, Avicenna asserts,
essence and existence are intensionally as well as extensionally
identical: God’s essence refers to nothing other than his existence.
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Avicenna 127
Although this appears on the surface to be a crucial move, and despite
the fact that later Muslim thinkers were intensely preoccupied with
determining the extent to which essence and existence really were
identical in God, Avicenna’s new argument, at least in the context
of the Metaphysics of The Healing, is not an indispensable component
of his general discussion there of the distinction between
the necessary of existence in itself and the possible of existence in
itself. This is because, as I already mentioned, that general discussion
is still framed in the terms Avicenna first set out in the Origin
and Destination, namely, that the basis for the distinction was
definitional.
In his last major work, the Pointers and Reminders, the two trends
inAvicenna’s articulation, justification, and use of the distinction all
come together in a terse synthesis. As he had in the Metaphysics of
The Healing, Avicenna discusses the distinction between necessary
and possible existence very soon after he discusses the distinction
between essence and existence. But in the Metaphysics of The Healing,
Avicenna’s general discussions of essence and existence (1.5)
and of necessary, possible, and impossible existence (1.6) were separated
by seven long sections from his proofs of God’s existence and
of God’s uniqueness as the only being that is necessary of existence
in itself (8.4). In the Pointers and Reminders, by contrast, Avicenna
moves straight from his discussions of essence and existence and
of necessary, possible, and impossible existence (interspersed with
some comments on the different categories of causes) to his proofs of
God’s existence and of God’s uniqueness. As a result the distinction
between essence and existence is pressed into immediate service,
now playing a fundamental role in the proofs of God’s existence and
of his uniqueness as the only being that is necessary of existence in
itself.
Legacy
As I mentioned above, Avicenna’s distinction between essence and
existence is more underdetermined, more variously interpretable,
than his distinction between the necessary of existence in itself and
the necessary of existence through another – possible of existence
in itself. This is not to say that the latter distinction was passed
on to subsequent thinkers in a fully crystallized form. On the contrary,
it created a number of philosophical problems, opportunities,
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
128 robert wisnovsky
and challenges to subsequent mutakallimu¯ n. One problem was that
God’s being necessary of existencemight imply a conceptual duality
in him, since there is a sense in which “necessary of existence” can
be understood as a species (albeit a species with only one individual
member) whose genus is “existent” (or “substance”) and whose
specific difference is “necessary.” Just as the species “human” is
notionally divisible into – and hence a composite of – the genus
“animal” and the specific difference “rational,” so too the species
“necessary of existence” will be notionally divisible – and hence a
composite of – the genus “existent” (or “substance”) and the specific
difference “necessary.”27 But once he was understood as a composite,
God no longer had any basis – any non-definitional basis, that is –
to claim sole occupancy of the category “uncaused being.” A second
problem is, should God’s existence be understood as an attribute
(s.
ifa) which is somehow additional to his self or essence, in the way
that Sunnı¯ mutakallimu¯ n understood God’s attributes of knowledge
(‘ilm), power (qudra) and life (h.
aya¯ t)? Should God’s existence be seen
instead as an accident of – and thus caused by – his essence? Or should
God’s essence and existence be taken to be wholly identical?28
Athird loose end is thatAvicenna seems to take for granted that (B)
“necessary of existence through another” and (C) “possible of existence
in itself” are convertible: that every existent that is (B) will
also be (C), and vice versa. The convertibility of (B) and (C) is certainly
plausible, even intuitive, in the case of concrete, extramental
existents (mawju¯ da¯ t fı¯ al-a‘ya¯n). But what about mental existents
(mawju¯ da¯ t fı¯ al-dhihn)? The answer I give will depend on other
interpretive commitments I have made. If, for example, my overriding
concern is to uphold Avicenna’s position (I) on essence and
existence – that essence and existence are intensionally distinct but
extensionally identical – then I shall tend to maintain that the existence
of an essence in the mind deserves to be called “existence”
just as much as the existence of an essence in the concrete, extramental
world does. (This is because I want to avoid holding the
Mu‘tazilite position that essences in the mind can be construed as
non-existent). And this tendency will further lead me in the direction
of assuming that Avicenna’s distinction between (A) “necessary
of existence in itself” and (B–C) “necessary of existence through
another” – “possible of existence in itself” will be just as applicable
to mental beings as it is to concrete existence. An important question
arises, however: what is the cause that makes a mental being
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Avicenna 129
“necessary of existence through another”? If the mental being is a
universal such as “Horse” or “Cat,” then the active intellect seems
the likeliest candidate to serve in the role of cause, since it is the
source of all forms in the sublunary world: it is the source of substantial
forms in the case of concrete beings such as the individuals
this horse and that cat, and it is the source of intelligible forms in the
case of mental beings such as the universals “Horse” and “Cat.” But
what about “Unicorn” and “Phoenix,” which are universals that it
is possible to conceive of, and which thus possess mental existence,
yet which are unrealizable as concrete, extramental beings – as the
individuals this unicorn or that phoenix? A further step leads us to
the problematic status of “Pentagonal House” (to use an example
Avicenna cites in a different context), which is a universal that it is
possible to conceive of, and which thus possesses mental existence,
but which (unlike “Unicorn” or “Phoenix”) might well exist someday
as a concrete, extramental being – as the individual this pentagonal
house – even though up to now (at least as far as Avicenna was
concerned) such a house has never existed concretely.
In the case of mental beings that are either unrealizable or as yet
unrealized in the concrete world – mental beings such as “Unicorn,”
“Phoenix,” or “Pentagonal House” – it is harder to determine which
cause makes them “necessary of existence through another.” Perhaps
the cause is still the active intellect; if that is so, the individuals
this unicorn and that phoenix will be unrealizable as concrete
beings (and this pentagonal house is as yet unrealized as a
concrete being) simply because the sublunary world happens to contain
no matter that is suitably disposed to receive those forms from
the active intellect. However, in the case of the intelligible forms
“Unicorn,” “Phoenix,” or “Pentagonal House,” as opposed to the
substantial forms that would inhere in this unicorn or that phoenix
or this pentagonal house, there are suitably disposed receptacles –
human intellects – that can and do receive what issues from the
Active Intellect. Alternatively, one might reasonably claim that in
the case of “Unicorn,” “Phoenix,” and “Pentagonal House,” it is
merely one of my soul’s internal senses that serves as the cause that
makes them “necessary of existence through another” – my faculty
of “rational imagination”, say, which can separate, juggle, and combine
different pieces of abstracted sense data.29 Of course, if I am
not so committed to promoting Avicenna’s position (I) on essence
and existence, I shall be tempted to avoid all the foregoing problems
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
130 robert wisnovsky
by clearly restricting the distinction between (A) and (B–C) to concrete,
extramental beings.30 But then I am still left with the original
problem: (B) and (C) will not be convertible, since there will be as
yet unrealized entities – “Pentagonal House,” for example – that are
possible of existence in themselves but that are not (yet) necessary
of existence through another.
Despite this problem, Avicenna’s analysis of God as the necessary
of existence presented a golden opportunity to Sunnı¯ mutakallimu¯ n
struggling with the troublesome consequences of their theory that
God’s attributes were, in some real sense, distinct from God’s self.
Before Avicenna came along, Sunnı¯ mutakallimu¯ n had treated eternality
(qidam) as the most important meta-attribute – the kind
of attribute that is predicable both of God’s self and of God’s
attributes. (This position emerged because the Sunn¯ıs, in contrast to
the Mu‘tazil¯ıs, were committed to the traditionalist notion that the
Qur’ ¯an, conceived of as God’s attribute of speech, was not created,
and hence was eternal.) But if all – or even some – of God’s attributes
are eternal, then a risk arose of seeming to allow for a multiplicity
of uncreated, eternal things, which in turn infringed upon God’s
uniqueness as the sole possessor of eternality, that ultimate criterion
of divinity which set him apart from all other beings, which are
temporally originated (muh. dath).
The post-Avicennian Sunnı¯ mutakallimu¯ n realized that necessity
of existence could also be conceived of as a meta-attribute, and one
with fewer problematic implications than eternality. God’s self is
necessary of existence, as are God’s attributes; yet the attributes
are not necessary of existence in themselves, since they are merely
attributes and thus, strictly speaking, not “selves” but only predicated
of selves. Instead, God’s attributes are necessary of existence
in (or with – the Arabic preposition bi-means both) his self.31 Other
Sunnı¯ mutakallimu¯ n realized that necessity of existence could be
construed as a mode of the copula that bound the attribute (understood
as a predicate) to God’s self (understood as subject).32
Any mutakallim, Sunn¯ı or Sh¯ı‘¯ı, interested in taking up
Avicenna’s new distinction still faced one crucial challenge. The
Qur’ ¯an describes God as possessing not only the attribute of causal
power (qudra), but also the attribute of will (ira¯da). One theme that
runs through much of the first part of Ghaz¯ al¯ı’s Incoherence of
the Philosophers is that Avicenna’s conception of the relationship
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Avicenna 131
between God and the world – a relationship between a being which
is necessary of existence in itself, and all other beings, which are
necessary of existence through another – robbed God of any true
agency. It is not enough, according to al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı, to conceive of God
merely as a cause; we must also conceive of God as an agent and
thereby make some room for God’s will. Al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı reckoned that
Avicenna expected too much from Muslim intellectuals, by forcing
them in effect to reduce all the names and acts of God so clearly
and powerfully described in the Qur’ ¯an to one single, simple name –
the necessary of existence in itself – and to one single, simple act –
self-intellection. What would be left of Islamic doctrine after such a
radical reduction?
In particular, Avicenna’s conception of the relationship between
God and the world entailed the denial of God’s most important
act, namely, his having created the world at some moment in the
past. This is because Avicenna’s distinction between the necessary
of existence in itself and the necessary of existence through another
was expressly designed not to map onto the mutakallimu¯ n’s distinction
between the eternal (qad¯ım) and the temporally originated
(muh. dath). Remember that one of Avicenna’s objectives was that his
new distinction would be able to differentiate between an uncaused
being – God – and all other, caused beings, eternal or temporally
originated.
The balancing act that preoccupied post-Avicennian mutakallimu
¯ n, both Sunnı¯ and Shı¯‘ı¯, was to make good use of Avicenna’s
compelling and innovative analysis of God as the only being which
is necessary of existence in itself, while at the same time ensuring
that they had not thereby committed themselves to the idea that God
necessitated the world’s existence. That is to say, the Sunn¯ı and Sh¯ı‘¯ı
mutakallimu¯ n were entirely comfortable appropriating and naturalizing
Avicenna’s analysis of God as the necessary of existence in
itself, as long as that formula was understood in an intransitive and
not a transitive way: it should point to God’s transcendence of and
separateness from the world, but not indicate the manner in which
God was causally involved with the world. The mutakallimu¯ n felt
that Avicenna’s distinction was useful because it provided the basis
for an excellent proof of God’s existence, and more generally because
it provided what appeared to be a watertight method of differentiating
between God’s existence and the world’s existence. But as an analysis
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
132 robert wisnovsky
of theway God causes the world’s existence, it required serious qualification,
since it could be taken to imply that God’s causation of the
world was no more than an involuntary act of necessitation, rather
than a voluntary act of agency.
At first glance, then, one of the great challenges of naturalization
facing the Sunnı¯ and Shı¯‘ı¯ mutakallimu¯ n of the post-Avicennian era
was to find some way to avoid throwing out the baby – the idea that
God is the only being that is necessary of existence in itself – when
they threw out the bathwater – the idea that God eternally necessitates
the world’s (eternal) existence. In fact, this was done with relative
ease. The Sunn¯ı-M¯atur¯ıd¯ı mutakallim al-Nasaf¯ı (d. 1114–15),
for example, incorporated Avicenna’s distinction into a section of
his Manifesto of the Proofs in which the compositeness of all beings
other than God – their being composed of motion and rest, or of
substance and accident – point to their not being necessary of existence
in themselves.33 And the Sh¯ı‘¯ı mutakallim¯ un H.
ill¯ı (d. 1326)
and La¯hı¯jı¯ (d. 1661) in their comments on al-T. u¯ sı¯’sOutline ofDogma
(Tajrı¯d al-i‘tiqa¯d, also known asOutline ofKala¯m– Tajrı¯d al-kala¯m),
both insist that asserting that God is necessary of existence in itself
does not entail God’s necessitation (ı¯ja¯b) of the world’s existence.34
T.
u¯ sı¯ himself had earlier tried to interpret Avicenna’s God as only an
efficient cause and not a final cause as well, probably because the
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |