petty kingdoms, as described by Ibn S.
¯a‘id, lasted during that of the
Almoravids in spite of the opposition of the preeminent scholars of
religious law (fiqh).
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Philosophy in Andalusia 157
Information about Ibn B¯ajja’s philosophical background is found
in an elaborate study of Ibn B¯ajja’s writings by the late Jam¯ al ad-
D¯ın al-‘Alaw¯ı,5 who tries to establish their chronology and, on this
basis, a developmental account of his thought. Al-‘Alaw¯ı takes into
consideration a letter Ibn Ba¯ jja sent to his friend Abu¯ Ja‘far Yu¯ suf ibn
H.
asday inwhich he explained that he first learned the mathematical
sciences, music, and astronomy. He went on to the study of logic
using the books of al-F ¯ar¯ab¯ı and finally devoted himself to physics,
the philosophy of nature. On the basis of his order of learning, al-
‘Alaw¯ı divides Ibn B¯ajja’s writings into three stages. His writings
on music, astronomy, and logic belong to the first stage; those on
natural philosophy to the second; and those most representative of
his thinking – the Rule of the Solitary,6 the Epistle of Conjunction,7
and the Farewell Message8 – to the third and last stage.
Philosophy and the classification of sciences
We may accept al-‘Alaw¯ı’s thesis for the purpose of analyzing Ibn
B¯ajja’s thought. Ibn B¯ajja followed other Andalusians in turning to
al-F ¯ar¯ab¯ı for logic, writing commentaries on his works without pretending
to be an independent logician. There are extant annotations
on the Categories, De Interpretatione, and both Analytics, and also
on the Introduction (a summary of Porphyry’s Isagoge) and the Five
Sections, two short texts of al-F ¯ar¯ab¯ı.9
Porphyry’s Isagoge was translated into Arabic by Abu¯ ‘Uthma¯n
Ya‘qu¯ b al-Dimashqı¯ and his translation was used by al-Fa¯ ra¯bı¯
in his Kit ¯ ab ¯Isa¯ ghu¯ jı¯, which he also calls Kita¯b al-madkhal
(Introduction).10 Ibn B¯ajja links the book to another by al-F ¯ar¯ab¯ı,
his Classification of the Sciences.11 In his Isagoge, Porphyry had
established five universal “meanings” or “sounds” – genus, species,
differentia, property, and accident – as the foundations of logic, the
highest development of which is the syllogism. Ibn B¯ajja goes in
another direction. He is more concerned with the arts that employ
syllogisms, and places his own classification of the sciences before
the exposition of the five universals: “it is in the nature of the syllogistic
arts to employ the syllogism once they are assembled and
completed, and not to have an action as their end.”12 The syllogistic
sciences are five, the first and most important ofwhich is philosophy,
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
158 josef puig montada
since it embraces all beings “insofar as it knows them with certain
science.” Thus two requirements are to be followed: certainty of
knowledge and universality of scope, and these requirements hold
for the five divisions of philosophy: metaphysics, physics, practical
philosophy, mathematics, and logic.
Metaphysics aims at those beings that are the ultimate causes;
they are neither a body nor in a body. Physics or natural science
aims at the natural bodies, the existence of which does not depend
on human will at all. Practical philosophy – which Ibn B¯ajja calls
“voluntary science” – aims at beings produced by the humanwill and
choice. Mathematics deals with beings abstract from their matters
and is divided into arithmetic, geometry, optics, astronomy, music,
the science of weights, and engineering, the “science of devices,”
which studies:
how to bring into existence many of the things proved theoretically in
mathematics, where the worth of the device consists in removing the hindrances
that perhaps hindered their existence. There are numerical devices
(like algebra), geometrical ones (like those for measuring the surface of bodies
impossible to access), astronomical devices, optical devices (like the art
of mirrors), musical and mechanical devices.13
Logic is the fifth and last division of philosophy and focuses on the
properties that beings acquire in the human mind; “because of such
properties and their knowledge [logic] becomes an instrument for
apprehending the right and the truth in beings.”14 Ibn B¯ajja remarks
that for this reason some people consider logic to be only an instrument
and not a part of philosophy, but insofar as these properties
have real existence, logic can be integrated into philosophy. He concludes
that logic is both part and instrument of philosophy.
Since a distinguishing feature of philosophy is the use of the apodictic
syllogism (burha¯n), the only one that yields certain knowledge,
not all syllogistic sciences can be considered parts of philosophy. Ibn
B¯ajja enumerates four such non-philosophical arts. Dialectic relies
only on opinion, and negates or asserts something through methods
of general acceptance. Sophistry aims at beings insofar as itmisrepresents
them and deceives us: itmakes the false look true, and the true,
false. And following the tradition initiated by the Greek commentators
on Aristotle, Ibn B¯ajja includes the Rhetoric and the Poetics in
the logic.15
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Philosophy in Andalusia 159
Nevertheless the classification of the sciences is not complete
because the aforementioned arts are all theoretical and arts like
medicine or agriculture were not considered. Ibn B¯ajja does not
admit these practical arts as syllogistic sciences: although they
make use of syllogisms, they employ them only “for the purpose
of certain activities [or tasks]” and neither medicine nor agriculture,
in their final shape, can be built on syllogisms. By contrast,
Ibn B¯ajja insists, the rules of optics or mechanics can be organized
by means of syllogisms. To sum up, according to Ibn B¯ajja, sciences
are first divided into those built on syllogisms and those
organized without syllogisms. Syllogistic sciences divide into philosophy,
dialectic, sophistic, rhetoric, and poetics. Philosophy subdivides
into demonstrative logic (the Prior and Posterior Analytics),
mathematics, natural philosophy, metaphysics, and practical
philosophy.
For Ibn B¯ajja the main purpose of the Isagoge is to explain the
concepts that underlie the ten Aristotelian categories, so that the
essence of the Kita¯b al-madkhal must be a theory of the individual
and the universal, which develops into an analysis of simple
and composite universal meanings, or intelligibles. Ibn B¯ajja shows
that the five predicables are not primitive concepts, but constitute
correlations between two universals falling within the rules of individuals
and classes. He says: “Genus, species, property, and accident
are correlates (ida¯ fa) which are inherent to the intelligibles regarding
the quantity of their subjects.”16 Genus, species, and property
are essences (ma¯hiyya¯ t) inhering in a shared subject; by contrast, the
accident is not an essence and exists outside the subject. The specific
difference is related only to the individual and may be grasped
without reference to the universal.
Ibn Ba¯ jja’s annotations to al-Fa¯ ra¯bı¯’s Kita¯b al-madkhal are more
innovative than they might seem at first. He is concerned to point
out that the Isagoge should not be limited to the exposition of the five
“sounds” – maybe six, if the individual is added17 – and that a science
is needed to lay the foundations for the Organon. He conceives this
science as a formal theory of individuals and classes, integrated into
the Porphyrian division and the principles of definition and description,
and thinks that this science should establish the ten categories.
Unfortunately he did not carry out his ideas and his words are only
a sketch of the theory.
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
160 josef puig montada
Philosophy of nature
Among Ibn B¯ajja’s contributions to the philosophy of nature, those
concerning movement are of great import; they are found mainly in
his Commentary on the Physics. Shlomo Pines introduced the term
“dynamics”18 to define his views, which no doubt were influenced
by the tradition linked to John Philoponus (d. ca. 566).19 Commenting
on Aristotle’s Physics, book VII, Ibn B¯ajja considers the claim that
everything is moved by something else, and says:
It is evident that the rest of the whole because of the rest of one of its parts,
takes place insofar as the movable is other than the mover, and when the
influence of the latter ends, it comes to rest. Its influence ends because the
mover ceases to act either on its own or because something else exerts resistance
on it. Whenever the mover ceases to act on its own, this happens due
either to its destruction, or to exhaustion (kala¯ l) of the power of the mover,
or because the cause disappears, or because the movement is complete, since
the movable has reached the end toward which it was moving.
The movements involved here are so-called “violent” movements,
as opposed to “natural” ones, discussed below. Ibn B¯ajja sketches a
theory of dynamics based on a notion of “power” different from the
Aristotelian notion of dunamis: they are mechanical forces which
can join another force or counteract it by offering resistance. There
is a minimum amount of moving power for each movable.20 For
instance, to move a boat a minimum of power is needed, otherwise
“one grain of sand could move the boat.” When two opposing
powers are equal, there is no movement, but when one power
“overcomes” the other, the body moves until it suffers “exhaustion”
(kala¯ l), because any bodymoved “violently” creates a contrary power
stronger than the one imposed by the mover, and also because the
imposed force becomes “exhausted.” The moving power is also subject
to time and distance factors and the mobile can offer almost no
resistance, so that absolute terms of proportionality do not apply.
Ibn B¯ajja analyzes “natural” movements too, such as a stone’s
falling through air and water. These movables need a moving power
capable not only of moving them but also of displacing the medium
they pass through. Dust particles stay suspended in the air because,
although they possess enough power to go down, the power is insufficient
to displace the air. Ibn B¯ajja differs here from Aristotle, who
thought the medium to be necessary for any natural movement, and
expresses the view that the medium is not a necessary condition,
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Philosophy in Andalusia 161
but only provides resistance. The different velocity with which the
stone passes through the air or the water is only caused by the different
density of the medium, it is not connatural to the medium. As a
proof that movement without any medium, namely, through a void,
is possible, Ibn B¯ajja adduces the movement of the spheres:
There [in the heavens] there are no elements of violent movement,
because nothing bends their movement, the place of the sphere remains the
same and no new place is taken by it. Therefore circular movement should
be instantaneous [if it were determined by the medium through which it
moved]. But we observe that some spheres move slowly – such as the sphere
of fixed stars – and others fast – the daily movement – and that there isneither
violence nor resistance among them. The cause for the different velocities
is the difference in nobility (sharf) between mover and movable.21
The role of the medium is not essential, but is only a kind of resistance,
and thus movement in the void is both theoretically possible
and confirmed by the observation of the spheres. Ibn B¯ajja contradicts
Aristotle and advances a doctrine that Galileo will prove to be
right.22 Once again he gives us only an outline, without undertaking
a deeper inquiry.
His theory of movement is the backbone of his philosophy of
nature, and has a further projection into metaphysics. In his epistle
On the Mobile,23 Ibn B¯ajja refers to his commentary on Aristotle’s
Physics where it has been proved that there is a First Mover causing
the eternal movement as well as numerous intermediate movers.
The souls of living beings count among those movers. But man’s soul
is characterized by the “deliberative movement” which is possible
because he is rational, and thus deliberates in order to achieve an
end. For the righteous soul this end is “absolute goodness” (al-khayr
‘al ¯ a al-it.
la¯q), andman is able to know the good abstract frommatter,
not only the good embedded in matter. While the soul is in a body,
the body is the instrument in which he moves toward this end, but
movement ceases once the soul has left the body and has become
identical with the pure forms: a process that we will examine in the
next section.
The metaphysics of forms
Ibn B¯ajja wrote several independent treatises on metaphysics, but
no commentary on Aristotle’s Metaphysics is extant, a fact already
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
162 josef puig montada
noted by his disciple ‘Al¯ı ibn al-Im¯am. Ibn B¯ajja’s treatise on the
Union of the Intellect withMan begins with an annotation on Metaphysics,
V.6, on the meaning of “one” or unity,24 but nothing else,
and we may raise the question why he did not write a full commentary
on the Metaphysics, given its importance. One reason could be
that the Aristotelian work does not fit well into the Neoplatonic
conception of philosophy, and of metaphysics as a means of ascent
to the highest principle and human happiness. Al-F¯ar¯ab¯ı had taught
that there is a descending procession from the One, and a corresponding
ascent available to the philosopher, while Avicenna linked
philosophy to the transcendent when he asserted that philosophy
has to achieve direct intellectual vision of the Necessary Being and
the forms that emanate from him.
Ibn B¯ajja takes up Aristotle’s theory of form but gives it a new
meaning, which is central to his system. Like his predecessors al-
F¯ar¯ab¯ı and Avicenna, he believes in an emanationist system inwhich
there is a First Being from whom the heavenly intelligences emanate
as far as the last one, the Active Intellect, which endows material
bodies with their forms. The most simple bodies are the four elements:
fire, air, water, and earth. Their forms are only pairs of the
opposite qualities hot–cold, moist–dry: for instance, water is cold
and moist. For Ibn B¯ajja these qualities are essentially powers, powers
that can cause motion.25 From these simple elements all natural
beings are generated and they receive more and more elaborate forms,
the most complex being souls. The simplest of souls is the nutritive
soul, the perfection of the body of a plant; it is followed by the sensitive
soul, belonging to animals, by the imaginative soul, which is
a perfection of men and animals that can make images out of earlier
sensations,26 and finally, by the rational soul. All are active forms,
i.e., powers and faculties, but only the rational soul goes beyond the
limits of the corporeal.
In his Treatise on the Spiritual Souls,27 which is the final section
of his book Rule of the Solitary, Ibn B¯ajja enumerates those forms
that are free of matter, in descending order:
The spiritual forms are of various kinds: the first kind are the forms of
the circular [i.e., heavenly] bodies, the second are the active intellect and
the acquired intellect, the third are the material intelligibles (ma‘qu¯ la¯ t), the
fourth are the intentions (ma‘a¯nı¯) existent in the faculties of the soul, i.e.,
existent in common sense, in the imaginative faculty, and in the memory.28
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Philosophy in Andalusia 163
“Spiritual” therefore applies broadly to every form that is not joined
to matter and is not separable from individual substance; the terminology
and doctrine echo those of Alexander of Aphrodisias. Spiritual
forms divide into universal and particular forms: particular forms
are found in the common sense, and are thus in a sense corporeal,
whereas universal forms are found only in the Active Intellect. Particular
spiritual forms may be true or false instantiations; they are
true only if their predicates exist in corporeal forms of individuals.
Forms thus have three degrees of existence: universal spiritual, particular
spiritual, and particular embodied forms.
Spiritual forms may produce a “state” (h.
a¯ l) in the soul, either a
state of perfection, as is produced by beauty, the fine arts, or noble
ascent, or of imperfection, produced by the opposite vices. Spiritual
forms, therefore, play a role in every aspect of human activity. Even
the inspiration received by the prophets belongs to the category of
particular spiritual forms, which do not pass through the common
sense, but are received directly from the Active Intellect. As for the
S.
u¯ fı¯s, their experiences belong to the level of the particular spiritual
forms, where common sense, imagination and memory are active.
But they mistake them for universal spiritual forms, and wrongly
believe that the coincidence of the three faculties is the source of
supreme happiness.29
Man has to organize his various faculties – from the rational down
to the nutritive – and there are categories of men according to the
prevalence of each of the three faculties. In some of them, corporeality
prevails, in a select few, spirituality does – Ibn B¯ajja counts
some ascetics and S.
u¯ fı¯s among the latter – but for most the situation
is mixed. Man is moved by spiritual forms that may be as basic
as clothing, housing, or food, but clothing, for instance, acts on two
levels, the protective and the ornamental. Virtues are attached to the
spiritual forms found in the imaginative faculty, because the purpose
of virtuous actions is generating positive feelings and admiration in
the souls of those who see them. The spirituality of most men is,
however, limited to particular forms, and only philosophers attain
the highest degree of spirituality, the immaterial and universal intelligibles
(akhlas. al-ru¯ h. a¯niyya¯ t). Although philosophers have to take
due care of the corporeal and particular spiritual forms, in order to
live, and live honorably, their main concern is the universal separated
forms:
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
164 josef puig montada
Spiritual acts render him more noble, and the intellectual acts render him
divine and virtuous. The man of wisdom is therefore necessarily a man who
is divine and virtuous. Of every kind of activity, he takes up the best only . . .
when he achieves the highest end – that is, when he apprehends the simple
substantial intelligences (‘uqu¯ l) that are mentioned in the Metaphysics, On
the Soul, and On Sense and the Sensible – he then becomes one of these
intelligences. It would be right to call him simply divine, and he will be
free from the mortal sensible qualities, as well from the [particular] spiritual
qualities.30
“Divine” here does not mean identicalwith God, but having Godlike
qualities, although his enemies could interpret such words as being
heretical. The philosopher has reached the highest point of human
wisdom, where it continues into the divine world.
Political philosophy
If we now contrast Ibn B¯ajjawith his master al-F ¯ar¯ab¯ı, we realize that
the philosopher has attained this degree of perfection while solitary,
without living in the virtuous city. At the beginning of The Rule of
the Solitary, Ibn B¯ajja explains the meaning of “rule” (tadb¯ır) as the
organization of actions toward an end; the proper “rule” is political,
an organization of the lives of the citizens in order to help them
to their perfection. Al-F¯ar¯ab¯ı, following Plato, had distinguished
four kinds of defective or sick cities or societies: the ignorant, the
wicked, the weakened, and the miscarried, as opposed to the perfect
city, whose success requires philosophers.31 Following him, Ibn B¯ajja
defines the virtuous city as one where its inhabitants do not need
physicians and judges: “love being the strongest bond between them,
there is no contention at all.”32 In the virtuous city all actions are
right: people avoid harmful foods and excessive drink, take physical
exercise, and always act honestly. The imperfect cities, however, do
need doctors, judges, and also “weeds” (nawa¯bit). “Weeds” are men
whose views are not the views of the majority; their idiosyncratic
opinions may be true or false, and those whose opinions are correct
are the cause for the coming-to-be of the perfect city in which there
is no disagreement. The solitary “weed” is the agent whose “rule” is
discussed by Ibn B¯ajja, who realized that the cities or societies of his
time belonged to the corrupted types and could not be rehabilitated.
He abandoned al-F ¯ar¯ab¯ı at this point and, as Steven Harvey puts it,
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |