44
‘A radical new view of human nature is emerging in the biological and
cognitive sciences and creating controversy
in intellectual circles, the
business community, and government. Recent discoveries in brain
science and child development are forcing us to rethink the long-held
belief that human beings are,
by nature, aggressive, materialistic,
utilitarian, and self-interested. The dawning realization that we are a
fundamentally empathic species has profound and far-reaching
consequences for society.’ (2010a, p.1)
Rifkin predicts that ‘we are at a decisive moment in the human journey where the
race to global empathic consciousness is running
up against global entropic
collapse.’ (2010a, p. 42) To support this view, Rifkin describes the history of
several civilizations and then explains the entropic biological, technological and
environmental changes that threaten the continuation
of civilization and may
undermine human nature and empathic capacities. Rifkin sees sympathy as passive
while empathy ‘conjures up active engagement – the willingness of an observer to
become part of another's experience, to share the feeling of that experience’ (2010a,
p. 12).
Rifkin does not stop at pointing out the importance of such conceived empathy for
the enjoyment and sharing of the experiences of others. He argues that world
leaders act on the basis of faulty assumptions about human nature. According to
Rifkin, the mistaken assumptions were lied down in the Enlightenment, at the dawn
of the modern market economy and the emergence of the nation state: that human
beings’ essential nature is rational,
detached, autonomous, acquisitive and
utilitarian and argued that individual salvation lies in unlimited material progress
here on Earth. Social neuroscience, and the discovery
of mirror-neurons in
particular, claims Rifkin, has forced us to re-evaluate this outdated view of human
nature. Given the economic and social problems we are facing, Rifkin says that
what is ‘required now is nothing less than a leap to global empathic consciousness
and in less than a generation.’ (2010b, p. 2)
Rifkin both envisages and describes empathy extended to all living things and the
biosphere in general. He quotes Maslow who said that ‘[m]ore sensitive observers
45
are able to incorporate more of the world into the self, i.e., they are able to identify
and empathize with wider and more inclusive circles of living and nonliving things’
(1969, p. 42) and contrasts this view with the Enlightenment ideas of human nature,
which, according to him did not give emotions their deserved place and importance.
While Rifkin sees the internet and other new communication technologies as the
technology that will aid the ‘radical leap,’ Savulescu and Persson (2012b)
add to
the discussion by proposing MB as a way of achieving moral outcomes.
There are many problems with Rifkin’s account. In the remaining parts of this
chapter I will address two. One problem has to do with the extreme view of the
utility (I dare to use this apparently
passe
Enlightenment concept) and sufficiency
of empathy in the making of a morally better world and agents. Rifkin (2010a),
Baron-Cohen (2011) and Savulescu and Persson (2012b) seem to advocate an
increase in empathy as a
panacea,
but such an indiscriminate increase in empathetic
sensitivity would hardly be conducive to moral outcomes.
Focusing on the notion
of empathetic distress, I will argue that while empathy might be conducive to moral
outcomes, Baron-Cohen’s equivocation of ‘more empathy’ with ‘morally better’ is
misguided. The second problem has to do with a more general equivocation of the
pro-social with moral. I will argue that Jotterand, Harris and others, are correct in
pointing out the importance of moral reasons in the quest for a better world and
better moral agents.
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: