50
any other cognitive and affective capacity: it is
multi-purpose, its effects are context
dependant and, in this context, more is not always better.
Rifkin (2010a) was wrong when he contrasted Maslows’ (1969) ‘new’ insight about
the importance of empathy with ‘emotionally incapable’ Enlightenment philosophy.
Hutcheson’s affective psychology and phenomenology developed in
Inquiry into
the Original of our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue
(1725),
Essay on the Nature and
Conduct of the Passions and Affectations
(1728a),
and
Illustrations on the Moral
Sense
(1728b) built on Shaftesbury’s notion of an inborn moral sense. Hutcheson
understood,
and held that, a crucial feature of our moral evaluation is that we
approve affections that are irreducibly benevolent and other-directed, at the same
time condemning inappropriately selfish ones while looking at how agent’s actions
flow from benevolent affect towards other sensitive beings. In turn,
Hume and
Smith built on Hutcheson’s ideas.
Hume locates all our motivations in the passions. Perhaps for this reason, he treats
the will in his discussion of the direct passions, identifying it as ‘the internal
impression we feel and are conscious of, when we knowingly give rise to any new
motion of our body, or new perception of our mind’ (
Treatise of Human Nature
1739-40, II.3.1 399, see also:
Dissertation on the Passions
in
Four Dissertations
1757,
Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals
, 1751).
Hume evokes the
importance of sympathy in his justification for the motivating character of what he
called ’artificial virtues:’ such as justice and promise keeping. The sentiment he
talks about, however, is ‘an extensive sympathy,’ redirected through general rules
and the social convention toward society as a whole. This sympathy in turn requires
correction, so that our sympathy is not directed only towards our kin. We have to
direct our passions beyond their natural bounds, so that it allows us
to approve of
the justice or honesty of all sorts of people in all sorts of situations, regardless of
their connection to us.
According to Hume, the general point of view does not provide a standard of
rationality but it does provide a standard of appropriateness –
and this standard
allows us to shape, cultivate and constrain our sentiments in ways that provide the
sort of stability and reliability that will form the basis of shared judgment. In
51
Theory of Moral Sentiments
Smith
responds, modifies and extends Hume’s account.
Although Smith discusses different ‘spectator positions’ one can adapt, the basic
idea that the ability to adopt the stance of spectator of
our actions and sentiments
means that we can evaluate and modify our emotional reaction.
Perhaps’ the sympathy of the ideal observer in Hume and Smith is too ‘passive’ for
Rifkin’s taste. Or perhaps it is too ‘active’ in its involvement of reflection. In
contrast to Rifkin (2010a) and Baron-Cohen (2011), Scottish Enlightenment
sentimentalists understood the importance of reflection and reason in morality, even
when, as for Hume, reason was only useful in establishing the ends.
9
Even
Hutcheson argued that although moral judgments ultimately rest in specific kinds of
emotions, the exercise of the benevolent moral sense calls for additional reflection
beyond
a certain element of reflections present in all our affections. Even this
minimal role of reason – well understood by the fathers of sentimentalism – seems
to escape the radical proponents of achieving moral and
planetary bliss through a
radical increase in empathy.
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: