as just so many separate personal goods. Whereas not to confirm our
sense of justice is to limit ourselves to a narrow view.
Finally, there is the reason connected with the Kantian interpretation:
acting justly is something we want to do as free and equal rational beings
(§40). The desire to act justly and the desire to express our nature as free
moral persons turn out to specify what is practically speaking the same
desire. When someone has true beliefs and a correct understanding of the
theory of justice, these two desires move him in the same way. They are
both dispositions to act from precisely the same principles: namely, those
that would be chosen in the original position. Of course, this contention is
based on a theory of justice. If this theory is unsound, the practical
identity fails. But since we are concerned only with the special case of a
well-ordered society as characterized by the theory, we are entitled to
assume that its members have a lucid grasp of the public conception of
justice upon which their relations are founded.
Let us suppose that these are the chief reasons (or typical thereof)
which the thin account of the good allows for maintaining one’s sense of
justice. The question now arises whether they are decisive. Here we
confront the familiar difficulty of a balance of motives which in many
ways is similar to a balance of first principles. Sometimes the answer is
found by comparing one balance of reasons with another, for surely if the
first balance clearly favors one course of action then the second will also,
should its reasons supporting this alternative be stronger and its reasons
supporting the other alternatives be weaker. But arguing from such com-
parisons presupposes some configurations of reasons which evidently go
one way rather than another to serve as a bench mark. Failing these, we
cannot get beyond conditional comparisons: if the first balance favors a
certain choice, then the second does also.
Now at this point it is obvious that the content of the principles of
justice is a crucial element in the decision. Whether it is for a person’s
good that he have a regulative sense of justice depends upon what justice
requires of him. The congruence of the right and the good is determined
by the standards by which each concept is specified. As Sidgwick notes,
utilitarianism is more strict than common sense in demanding the sac-
rifice of the agent’s private interests when this is necessary for the greater
happiness of all.
32
It is also more exacting than the contract theory, for
while beneficent acts going beyond our natural duties are good actions
and evoke our esteem, they are not required as a matter of right. Utilitari-
32.
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: