The Invisible Constitution in Comparative Perspective



Download 4,63 Mb.
Pdf ko'rish
bet81/366
Sana18.08.2021
Hajmi4,63 Mb.
#150519
1   ...   77   78   79   80   81   82   83   84   ...   366
Bog'liq
The Invisible Constitution in Comparative Perspective by Rosalind Dixon (editor), Adrienne Stone (editor) (z-lib.org)

Kirk v. Industrial Court of New South Wales (2010) 239 CLR 531, 566, 580.

44 


Pointless rather than false in this case because s. 73, like the Ninth Amendment, is directive 

rather than an assertion of a proposition.

45 

See S. McDonald, ‘“Defining Characteristics” and the Forgotten “Court”’ (2016) 38 Sydney 



Law Review 207.


 

The Implicit and the Implied in a Written Constitution 

121


Commission . . .’). The presupposition in s. 73 (iii) that it exists has not been 

thought to imply that it must exist.

It therefore seems that any implication that State Supreme Courts must 

continue to exist must be due either to some other kind of implication, or 

special legal interpretive principles concerning the purpose of s. 73 (ii) and 

what is necessary to fulfil it.



4.4.2. Implicatures

‘Implicature’ is a term famously coined by the philosopher H. P. Grice, build-

ing on the verb ‘to implicate’ (meaning ‘to imply’). As an example, Grice 

described a Philosophy Professor, asked to provide a reference for a student 

seeking a lectureship in philosophy, replying that ‘he writes good English and 

regularly attends tutorials’.

46

 The statement damns with faint praise – it ‘impli-



cates’ that the student has no philosophical ability worth mentioning.

Grice’s explanation of how we identify implicatures relied on the commu-

nicative principles mentioned previously, of quantity, quality, relevance and 

manner.


47

 But he argued that there need only be general, rather than univer-

sal, compliance with these principles. Speakers and authors can communicate 

something sub silentio by blatantly flouting one of the principles at the level 

of express meaning. The express meaning of the Professor’s reference, which 

says nothing about the student’s philosophical ability, plainly flouts the prin-

ciples requiring quantity and relevance. But the recipient of the reference, 

assuming the Professor nevertheless intended to communicate something 

helpful, understands this to be deliberate and itself pregnant with meaning: 

the Professor is taken to implicate that the student has no philosophical abil-

ity worth mentioning. The Professor exploited the communicative principles, 

conveying an implicature by appearing on the surface to flout them.

Some other suggested examples of such exploitation involve nonliteral but 

direct speech rather than implicature, which is a form of indirect speech. 

Consider figurative statements that are metaphorical (‘Juliet is the sun’) or 

ironical (‘That was clever’, said after a foolish mishap). Because their literal 

meanings would obviously violate the principle requiring truthfulness, they 

are interpreted as conveying some other meaning.

48

 As previously noted, most 



elliptical expressions can probably be analysed in a similar fashion (consider, 

again, ‘Everyone has gone to Paris’).

46 

Grice, Supra note 33, 33, 37.



47 

See Supra, text to nn 33 to 34.

48 

But see Bach, Supra note 21, 143–4.




122 

Jeffrey Goldsworthy

Lawyers usually attempt to be as explicit as possible to avoid any chance 

of misunderstanding. It is therefore extremely rare to find in constitutions 

examples of deliberate insinuations or hints, intended to be read ‘between 

the lines’, such as the one conveyed by the Professor’s reference. One of the 

rare examples may be the way the American Constitution appears to deal with 

slavery by carefully using euphemisms, rather than the word itself.

49

Nevertheless, legal texts may include other kinds of implicatures, which 



result from the likelihood that the speaker or author has complied with, rather 

than flouted, Grice’s principles of communication.

Consider the following sign: ‘Children under 15 years admitted free’. Its 

express meaning is consistent with children of fifteen years or over also being 

admitted free: it does not expressly rule that out. But it suggests that only chil-

dren under fifteen will be admitted free, because otherwise it would violate 

the communicative principle of quantity. Readers presume that such a sign 

is fully informative as to free admission, rather than disclosing only part of 

the policy to be applied. If children of fifteen or over, or adults, were also 

admitted for free, the sign would violate that principle and would be seriously 

misleading. If everyone were admitted free, it would be worse than pointless. 

The sign is therefore understood either as elliptical (‘[Only] children under 

fifteen years admitted free’), or as implicating that no one else is admitted free.

The interpretive presumption expressio unius est exclusio alterius (‘the 

expression of one thing is the exclusion of another’) embodies the legal equiv-

alent of the same kind of inference.

50

 It is applied to written constitutions, as 



well as to statutes, and in both cases to procedures, rights and powers.

As for procedures, consider provisions that authorise constitutional amend-

ments. Section 128 of the Australian Constitution expressly provides that ‘This 

Constitution shall not be altered except in the following manner’, which it goes 

on to prescribe. But even if it had merely said ‘This Constitution may be altered 

in the following manner’, that manner would arguably – by an inference of 

the expressio unius kind – be exclusive. The provision would be elliptical, the 

word ‘only’ being regarded as implicitly qualifying the words ‘may be altered’.

It is interesting to compare Article V in the United States Constitution, 

which sets out the procedure for constitutional amendment without expressly 

providing that it is exclusive:

The Congress, whenever two thirds of both houses shall deem it necessary

shall propose amendments to this Constitution, or, on the application of the 

49 


See discussion in R. Barnett, ‘The Misconceived Assumption about Constitutional Assump-

tions’ (2009) 103 Northwestern University Law Review 615, 644–50.

50 

For useful discussion see A.  Scalia and B. A.  Garner, Reading Law: The Interpretation of Legal 



Texts (St Paul: West, 2012), 107–11.


 


Download 4,63 Mb.

Do'stlaringiz bilan baham:
1   ...   77   78   79   80   81   82   83   84   ...   366




Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©hozir.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling

kiriting | ro'yxatdan o'tish
    Bosh sahifa
юртда тантана
Боғда битган
Бугун юртда
Эшитганлар жилманглар
Эшитмадим деманглар
битган бодомлар
Yangiariq tumani
qitish marakazi
Raqamli texnologiyalar
ilishida muhokamadan
tasdiqqa tavsiya
tavsiya etilgan
iqtisodiyot kafedrasi
steiermarkischen landesregierung
asarlaringizni yuboring
o'zingizning asarlaringizni
Iltimos faqat
faqat o'zingizning
steierm rkischen
landesregierung fachabteilung
rkischen landesregierung
hamshira loyihasi
loyihasi mavsum
faolyatining oqibatlari
asosiy adabiyotlar
fakulteti ahborot
ahborot havfsizligi
havfsizligi kafedrasi
fanidan bo’yicha
fakulteti iqtisodiyot
boshqaruv fakulteti
chiqarishda boshqaruv
ishlab chiqarishda
iqtisodiyot fakultet
multiservis tarmoqlari
fanidan asosiy
Uzbek fanidan
mavzulari potok
asosidagi multiservis
'aliyyil a'ziym
billahil 'aliyyil
illaa billahil
quvvata illaa
falah' deganida
Kompyuter savodxonligi
bo’yicha mustaqil
'alal falah'
Hayya 'alal
'alas soloh
Hayya 'alas
mavsum boyicha


yuklab olish