7.6.4. Ghost in the God Machine: Who is dominating?
Action without a name, a ‘who’ attached to it, is meaningless.
Arendt, 1958,
The Human Condition
36
We’d assume that the enhanced society is not blind to Clarke’s HAL-9000 lessons.
168
Max Weber held that the existence of domination requires ‘the actual presence of
one person successfully issuing orders to others’ (1968, p. 53). On such a narrow
conception, the pertinent question will not be about the domination of the God
Machine, but rather who the God Machine serves and who controls it. Broader
conceptions of domination may not require a specific agent ‘issuing orders.’ For
example, domination may arise from the inadvertent and unconscious actions of
agents as a by-product of social and economic forces (e.g. Shapiro, 2012).
However, even here it is not the social and economic forces that are dominating –
as domination presupposes a degree of agency that social, economic and natural
forces do not have.
The extent to which the notion of agency is central to the political idea of freedom
as non-domination is already indicated in Pettit’s explication of the idea of
domination. In Pettit’s words, an agent is dominating when an agent has:
‘1. the capacity to interfere
2. with impunity and at will
3. in certain choices that the other is in a position to make’ (Pettit 1997, pp. 578-
581).
To interfere in this sense ‘with impunity’ is to do so without ‘penalty,’ be it
resistance by the victim or punishment by some external authority (Pettit, 1997, p.
580). To interfere ‘at will’ is, according to Pettit, to do so at one’s own pleasure or
whim. In other words, the interferer has the necessary ‘discretion’ to act as he or
she chooses (Pettit, 1997, pp. 580-587). Does the God Machine have a capacity to
interfere at one’s own pleasure or whim? I very much doubt that Savulescu and
Persson’s (2012a) God Machine experiences much pleasure or is capable of whims
in any sense stronger than in an anthropomorphising metaphorical sense, similar to
the way in which we are subject to ‘the whims of Nature.’ Similarly, I very much
doubt that the ‘penalties’ Pettit refers to would have much impact on the God
Machine – for a simple and sufficient reason that the God Machine is not the kind
of agent that non-domination freedom theories refer to.
On the non-domination conception of freedom, it is not the ‘laws of slavery’ that
dominate the slaves but rather slave owners, who are effectively allowed to do so
169
by the absence of effective laws that would curtail their arbitrary power. Similarly,
to the extent that the God Machine is an analogy for state power and law, it is not
the God Machine who dominates the citizens of society. In a more technologically-
fuelled example, drones flying the sky above the Afghanistan-Pakistan border do
not dominate the local people. It is those who steer the drones, those who establish
targets, those whose power the drones enable, further and protect.
37
But perhaps the God Machine is better seen as the analogy for the state. What are
we to make of the state, ontologically? According to Hegel, the state was the
‘Divine Idea on Earth’ (1837, p.39). Hobbes (1651) used the metaphor of an
‘Artificial Man’. Nietzsche declared it the ‘coldest of all cold monsters’ (1883, p.
160), although we would be hard pressed to take Nietzsche’s statement in his highly
poetic work literally. John of Salisbury (1159) defines the republic as a ‘certain
body’ and takes his anatomical metaphor rather far, perhaps sheltered by his
reference to Plutarch:
38
The place of the head in the body of the commonwealth is filled
by the prince, who is subject only to God and to those who
exercise His office and represent Him on earth, even as in the
human body the head is quickened and governed by the soul.
The place of the heart is filled by the Senate, from which
proceeds the initiation of good works and ill. The duties of eyes,
ears, and tongue are claimed by the judges and the governors of
provinces. Officials and soldiers correspond to the hands. Those
who always attend upon the prince are likened to the sides.
Financial officers and keepers
1
(I speak now not of those who
are in charge of the prisons, but of those who are keepers of the
privy chest) may be compared with the stomach and intestines,
which, if they become congested through excessive avidity, and
37
I do not wish to make claims about the arbitrariness of the military intervention in
Afghanistan or in Pakistan. The presence of drones is a good illustration of the agents-
instruments distinction, on which I wish to focus. For the purpose of this argument assume
that the intervention would not fulfil the conditions necessary for non-arbitrariness or
appropriate control.
38
Which was most likely what scholars have kindly described as literary device, see:
Canning (1996, p. 112).
170
retain too tenaciously their accumulations, generate innumerable
and incurable diseases, so that through their ailment the whole
body is threatened with destruction. The husbandmen
correspond to the feet, which always cleave to the soil, and need
the more especially the care and foresight of the head, since
while they walk upon the earth doing service with their bodies,
they meet the more often with stones of stumbling, and therefore
deserve aid and protection all the more justly since it is they who
raise, sustain, and move forward the weight of the entire body.
Take away the support of the feet from the strongest body, and it
cannot move forward by its own power, but must creep painfully
and shamefully on its hands, or else be moved by means of brute
animals.
However, for Wendt, a political scientist and a social constructivist international
relations scholar, the state
is
a person. Wendt argues that it is not that the state ‘is
like’ a person, it literally is a person: ‘states are people too’ (1999, p. 215). It is
understandable that the problem of defining state agency emerged in the field of
international relations with considerable force, where treating states as agents
conferred descriptive ease yet influenced the kind of descriptions, explanations and
predictions scholars would make (Wendt, 1987). In positivist explanations of the
relation between the citizen and the state, personification of the state was treated as
a useful metaphor – it was understood as an instrumental device aimed at
facilitating explanation and implied no ontological commitment to the state actually
possessing any of the properties assigned to it. To put it in the words of Gilpin,
when we talk of ‘the state acting,’ we engage in a collective illusion (1986, p. 318):
we all know that the state does not really act and we also know that in reality there
is no such thing as a state.
There are two separate questions here. First is the question of ontology: whether or
not the state exists; is the state real, is it a fiction, or is it a theoretical abstraction?
The second question concerns the kind of properties that make sense to ascribe to
states (and, in our discussion, the God Machine): is a state (and the God Machine)
an agent, or, to put it more strongly, a kind of agent that can dominate in a sense
171
that is relevant to freedom by non-domination?
39
I will briefly consider the second
question as more relevant to the issue at hand.
What kind of agency is necessary for Sparrow’s objection to succeed? To answer
that question let us look closer at the notion of agency accommodated by Pettit’s
(1997) theory. Petitt himself attempts to apply freedom as non-domination to
international relations and relations between state and non-state entities (Kukathas
and Pettit 1991; Pettit 2010). In response to the agent/structure problem, he
explicitly falls on the ‘agent’ side of the distinction:
‘while a dominating party will always be an agent – it cannot just be a
system or a network or whatever – it may be a personal or a corporate
or collective agent’ (Pettit, 1997, p. 52).
He recognizes the challenge of normative individualism, which he understands as a
position that holds that ‘there can be no difference in the value of two institutional
arrangements unless there is a difference in the value for individual human beings
of those arrangements’ (Pettit, 2010). His justification for the extension of the non-
domination view of freedom to the business of what he calls ‘agencies’ (such as
states, corporations and non-governmental organisations) and its normative
importance, however, explicitly rests on the idea that the agency of collectives is
rooted in the agency of the people that constitute them:
‘the domination of corporate agencies will matter insofar as those
agencies are organizations whereby individual human beings
combine to act together. If the things that the members do as a
corporate entity are subject to the alien control of another agent or
agency, then those members are themselves subject to alien
control.’ (2010, p. 76)
Pettit’s (1997) theory is built on a conception of domination as a relation between
persons, or groups of agents that are capable of exhibiting collective intentionality.
He proposes that a
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |