215
do not deny that deliberation oriented
towards practical action, revising one’s
beliefs and developing new ones is also immensely valuable insofar as it translates
into action. However, I doubt that it is the only (or perhaps even the most) effective
way of making our rationally endorsed beliefs ‘sink in.’
This empirical claim needs some more support. Psychology in its therapeutic aspect
is perhaps the discipline most concerned
with the kind of behavioural change we
are talking about here (although usually more aimed at increasing well-being). The
history of psychology reflects the above tension between the importance of insight
into the sources, causes, functions and mechanics of particular behaviours
(including the associated beliefs) and its aim of changing problematic behaviours
and alleviating distress (Friedman, 2011). There
is no need to discuss this
controversy in detail. For the purpose of our discussion it is sufficient to simply
refer to the gap familiar to psychotherapists
: the gap between insight and
behavioural or emotional change.
Admittedly, the concept of ‘insight’ as used in psychology and psychiatry is
somewhat vague and used to describe a variety of phenomena. However, even with
this limitation in mind, it seems to encompass the belief
change that results from
deliberation and reflection and is thus applicable to the matter discussed here.
Measures of ‘insight’ used in cognitive-behavioural therapy, for example, include
‘becoming aware of one’s beliefs’ or ‘identification of errors in thinking’ (Tang and
DeRubeis, 1999). In turn, the measurement of ‘insight’ used in more
psychodyamically oriented approaches relies on the estimate of the patient’s
understanding of his internal conflicts, associated problems, reoccurring behaviours
and associations with previous experiences and includes the awareness of the
connected beliefs (Johansson et al., 2010).
The
psychoanalytical tradition typically attributed a considerable potential of
therapeutic change to insight. For a long time, behaviour
change was seen as a
natural consequence and an integral part of a so called ‘true’ insight (Sandler, Dare,
and Holder, 1973). This way of thinking is difficult to uphold in light of current
empirical examinations of the effects of therapy, as an observable therapeutic
change often occurs only some time after achieving insight – and sometimes does
not occur at all (see Høgland et al., 1994). Additionally, it is unclear to what extent
216
the change was brought about by insight alone, and to what extent by other,
mediating factors, initiated by the insight or co-occurring with it. In fact, empirical
research comparing the treatment outcomes of cognitive
behavioural therapy with
more behaviourally oriented approaches indicates that the ‘cognitive’ aspects of
cognitive-behavioural therapy are less obviously effective than the behavioural
components. Moreover, psychologists of various traditions often distinguish
between what they call ‘intellectual insight’ and ‘emotional insight’, with only the
latter thought to be accompanied by change in behaviour (for review see: Elliott et
al., 1994). Although the concepts employed here admittedly are not very sharp, I
think that even this crude distinction gets at an important
observation repeatedly
made by those professionally in the business of reflectively-embedded behavioural
change: that there is a gap between consciously held beliefs and their impact on
everyday behaviour. This gap is present in our everyday lives, but becomes
especially vivid in the context of change.
There are limitations to drawing inferences from psychotherapy in discussing
bettering moral agency and MB. The goal of therapy is different than moral
enhancement aimed at making better moral agents. One would have to look more
closely at the exact constructs evaluated to draw any strong conclusions. Discussion
of particular therapeutic tools would ground a stronger argument.
The assessment
of particular aspects of therapy contributing to change is in its infancy, etc. As a
result, the data from empirical evaluations is not sufficient to provide a basis for a
strong claim that methods other than belief change should be prioritized. However,
empirical evaluations of various methods of therapy still provide the best and most
ecologically valid evidence we have for the effect of change in beliefs specifically –
insofar as we expect the change of moral beliefs to be followed by change in action.
As it stands today, the research supports the weaker claims I wish to make – that
there is a gap between the reflectively endorsed beliefs and everyday behaviour,
that this gap is common enough (as I suggest) to warrant attention, and that it is not
best addressed by
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: