207
require a person to be in a particular internal state. While ‘it is possible to do
something grammatical either by chance or under the guidance of another’ (NE,
1105a22-23) virtue requires more – and that more includes the right inclinations
and an appropriate cooperation of inclination and reason (NE, 1105a28-30). Right
inclinations, even if sufficiently fine-tuned, are not sufficient for virtue on their
own. As a result, MB on its own will never be able to create a virtuous person on
Aristotle’s account, and thus ‘manufacturing virtue’, is not an option – at least as
far as Aristotelian virtue in concerned.
However, the right habits and inclinations do contribute to virtuous character. A
virtuous
person knows the good, acts according to the good and her reason is in
harmony with inclinations. In Aristotle's words, the non-rational part of a virtuous
person's soul ‘speaks with the same voice’ (
homophônei,
NE
,
1102b28) as the
rational part. In contrast to a virtuous person, an enkratic or continent person knows
the good, acts according the good but needs to conquer the passions that nudge
towards the bad.
Akrasia involves acting against one's better judgement.
56
An
akratic person is someone who because of his feelings abandons himself against
correct reason.
According to Aristotle, emotion challenges reason in three ways. In both the akratic
and the enkratic, it competes with reason for control over action. Second, in the
akratic, it temporarily
robs reason of its full acuity, thus handicapping it as a
competitor for control over actions – it keeps reason from fully exercising its
power.
57
Third, passion can make someone impetuous; here victory over reason is
so powerful that the decision does not enter the arena of conscious reflection until it
is too late to influence action.
56
This is the standard view of akrasia. It is not universally shared, however. Perhaps the
earliest philosophical discussion of akrasia is in Plato’s (1996)
Protagoras,
where Socrates
argues, in effect,
that akrasia is impossible, since no one ever knowingly chooses to do
wrong. All apparent cases of akrasia are in fact cases of weakness of will. Another account
is that of Watson (2004) who questions the clarity of the distinction between
(blameworthy) akrasia and (blameless) compulsion.
57
According to Aristotle, Socrates argued that there is no akrasia understood as weakness
of will. A similar position was put forward by Hare (1952).
When reason remains
unimpaired and unclouded, its dictates will carry us all the way to action, save for practical
obstacles. It is only the clouded judgement that makes a person akratic. I follow Aristotle in
disagreeing with Socrates and Hare: I think that the example of OCD convincingly
demonstrates that weak willed akrasia is possible.
208
Aristotle’s emotions and appetites (
pathos
) do not necessarily translate into strong
psychological forces:
anger is a
pathos
whether it is weak or strong. Aristotle
clearly indicates that it is possible for an akratic person to be defeated by a
weak
pathos
– the kind that most people would easily be able to control. Thus, it is
not the strength of emotion or inclination itself, but rather the ratio between the
reasoned control and the behaviour resulting from passions that matters – this latter
type of akrasia involves the passions ‘overtaking’ reason.
Aristotle’s account considers virtue, enkrateia, akrasia
and vice as properties of
character. Consistently with this, Aristotle describes an akratic individual, an
individual who more commonly than others succumbs to passions and appetites
instead of following reason. Following more recent discussions on akrasia, I will
focus on those
concepts as applying to
actions
instead of
agents
. I will often talk
about ‘desires’ and ‘inclinations’, but the same considerations apply to
biomedically modifiable undepinnings of action in so far as they give rise to
desires.
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: