Muslim philosophers to reunite these various traditions, and it is
clear from the language he uses that Plato was the central hero of his
philosophy.13
Though there is much of the mythical in Suhraward¯ı’s account
of the history of philosophy, it deserves some consideration both
on historical and philosophical grounds. First some comments and
clarifications. The Ionian physicists are ignored, although they were
known to Muslimphilosophers through doxographies, Aristotle, and
the Galenic tradition. There are also no Christians or Muslims,
except for theS.
u¯ fı¯s, and these do not include the individuals usually
listed as the founding fathers of Islamic mysticism. The Persians
are not historical Zoroastrian priests but legendary Persian kings
and viziers, understood as sages. The connections to the Orientals –
Persians, Indians, and Chinese – are much vaguer than those to the
Greeks. As for the Greeks, Suhraward¯ı’s “divine philosophers” are
what the doxographers called “the Italian School.” The historical
Socrates and Plato obviously had connections to both the Ionians
and the Italians, but I think that Suhraward¯ı was correct to say that
Plato should be thought of primarily as a successor of Empedocles
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Suhraward¯ı 207
and Pythagoras rather than of Thales and the Ionians. Moreover, the
view that the Egyptian alchemists preserved a pre-Platonic philosophical
tradition that they passed on to the Muslims has recently
found a scholarly defender.14 Both the occult sciences and medicine
transmitted Greek thought to the Muslims in parallel to the translations
of Aristotle and other philosophers.15
Suhraward¯ı’s interest in his philosophical genealogy, its “Oriental”
connections, and many of its details are characteristic of the
whole Pythagorean/Platonic/Neoplatonic tradition. Plato, Porphyry,
Iamblichus, and Renaissance and early modern Neoplatonists like
Bruno were all interested in ancient wisdom, Oriental wisdom, and
particularly Egyptian wisdom. They were all interested in the allegorical
interpretation of classic texts. There was a consistent interest
in occult sciences and their practical application. Members of this
tradition believed that truth is primarily to be found in anintelligible
world, accessible to us only through some sort of intellectual or mystical
intuition and accessible only imperfectly. The product of such
intuition can be conveyed only through language that is symbolic to
one degree or another. The mythical systems of other peoples presumably
represent the intuitions of their sages. Ancient Egypt, with
its rich mythology and evocative hieroglyphs, exercised a unique
fascination.16
the nominalist intuition and the critique
of avicenna
The explanation that a philosopher gives of the universe and our
knowledge of it depends very much on how he is inclined to see the
world when he starts out; one is born a Platonist or Aristotelian, it is
said. For Suhraward¯ı the relevant fact is that the world stands present
to us as distinct manifest concrete things having particular qualities.
It may be that it is only after rigorous training that we learn to see
everything that is before us – he is a mystic, after all – but even our
knowledge of God and the metaphysical foundations of the universe
is not a matter of laborious construction and deduction but of learning
to see what is always before us. We see what is concrete, and it
is the concrete thing that is real, not the metaphysical ingredients
whose existence we might infer. Thus in metaphysics Suhraward¯ı
rejects realism with regard to universals, holding that everything
that exists is a particular; in this he may be compared to nominalists
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
208 john walbridge
like Ockham. And in epistemology he holds that knowledge
consists in immediate awareness; in this he may be compared
to empiricists like Berkeley and Hume. Like the nominalists and
empiricists he is suspicious of metaphysical constructs and thus is
more zealous as a philosophical critic than as a constructor of systems.
Given the way that Suhraward¯ı has usually been portrayed,
these claims need to be defended.17
The place to start is where Suhraward¯ı himself claimed to have
started – with the doctrine that later came to be known as “knowledge
by presence.” The dominant epistemological theory among
Muslim philosophers of Suhraward¯ı’s time was that of Avicenna,
which in turn derived from the theory of cognition in Aristotle’s De
Anima. In this Peripatetic epistemology, as Suhraward¯ı would have
called it, our senses are affected by external stimuli. The resulting
forms are imprinted somehow in the sense organs and then are combined
in the brain and manipulated in various ways to produce the
objects of sensation and imagination. Objects of pure thought – the
concept of triangle, for example – cannot simply be imprinted in
the brain since any imprinted triangle must necessarily be the
image of some particular triangle with particular angles and sides
of particular length. Such abstract ideas must therefore be in the
immaterial mind, which has the capacity to become the idea of
triangle. The idea of triangle comes into being in the immaterial
intellect through the contemplation of the particular triangles presented
to it by the senses and the related material faculties of the
brain. The intellect is thus able to recognize the pure essences of
things in the material images presented to it by the senses and the
brain. These then become the raw materials of the sciences and real
knowledge.18
There are difficulties, however, as anyone who has wrestled with
Aristotle’s accounts of cognition can testify. The theory explains
how we know universals once we know them but not how we come
to know universals nor how we know particulars beyond the level of
sensation. The obvious problem is that the theory seems to require
that we can recognize the essences of natural kinds by inspection and
know immediately what those essences consist in. This is plausible
if we are talking about triangles, but Aristotle developed the theory
for natural science and biology. We should thus know that human
beings are rational animals by meeting various human beings and
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Suhraward¯ı 209
know by inspection that bats and horses belong to the same class,
mammals, but that bats and birds are in quite different classes. This
implausibility has always dogged the Peripatetic scientific project,
despite Aristotle’s attempt to address the problem in Posterior
Analytics, II.19. From an Islamic point of view the greater difficulty
is that we cannot have intellectual knowledge of particulars. We
know geometry as immaterialminds, but we know the things around
us as material beings, in the same way that animals do. We might
live with the implausibility of knowing the diagram in a geometry
book in a completely different way than we know the theorem illustrated,
but the theory also implies that God cannot know particulars.
Averroes responded that God knew things through their causes, but
this does not seem too convincing.19
Suhraward¯ı started over with the phenomenon of vision, the
noblest of the senses and the usual, if not always acknowledged,
starting point for theories of knowledge. There had been for centuries
two contradictory theories of vision – extramission and intromission.
In the one a cone went out from the eye and contacted the
objects of vision; in the other something came in from the things
seen and affected the eye. The former lent itself to mathematical
optics but was physically implausible. The latter was more plausible
physically, even if no one had quite worked out the details, but it
had mathematical problems. Both theories had difficulties explaining
how light made it possible to see things. (The theory of Ibn al-
Haytham, or Alhazen, which is more or less correct, was not yet
widely known.) Suhraward¯ı pointed out that both theories missed a
fundamental point, that we see things, not the images of things. We
see a large mountain that is far away, not a small image in the eye.
We see whiteness whether or not it is brightly illumined. Actually,
vision is simple, Suhraward¯ı tells us. It consists of a sound eye being
in the unveiled presence of something illumined. Light is simply that
which makes something manifest. Most important, vision requires a
self-aware being. The other senses are analogous. Obviously, a completely
worked out Illuminationist theory of vision would require
us to take account of the mechanics of perspective and the eye, but
Suhraward¯ı has made an important point, that the critical element in
sensation is that there is awareness by a conscious being of the thing
that is the object of sensation. That awareness is what distinguishes
a human being seeing from a movie camera.20
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
210 john walbridge
He then extends this theory to knowledge in general. In the
famous dream, Aristotle had told him that the key to understanding
knowledge was self-knowledge. Knowledge, like vision, consists
in the unveiled presence of the object of knowledge before the selfaware
knower. Later Illuminationists refer to this as the unity of the
knower, knowledge, and object of knowledge, but this formulation
misses the point that I think is important – that knowledge is of
particular things that can be apprehended directly. Being a mystic,
Suhraward¯ı did not think that the objects of the senses were the only
things that could be apprehended. We can, with suitable training,
apprehend the immaterial beings – the angels and Platonic Forms.
Nevertheless, these too are particulars (on Forms as particulars, see
further below). The whole theory is nominalism of a thoroughly radical
sort.21
This nominalism is the basis for his attack on the Peripatetic theory
of essential definition. Aristotle, followed by his Islamic disciples,
had held that the essences of things are made known by essential
definitions, h.
udu¯ d in Arabic. Such definitions consist of the genus
plus the differentia – “man is a rational animal,” for example. Other
kinds of definitions might succeed in identifying a natural kind –
“man is a laughing biped” – but they do not make the essence known.
If we know the differentia, we effectively already know the thing, but
in practice we can never know whether we have exhausted the differentia
of a particular kind. Moreover, many Peripatetic definitions
turn out to be more obscure than what they define. “Black gathers
vision,” but, of course, anyone who can see knows what black is. If
he doesn’t, it can be pointed out to him. Since Aristotle andAvicenna
identify essential definition as the way by which concepts must be
conveyed, Suhraward¯ı concludes that the Peripatetics have made it
impossible to know anything.22
the metaphysics of illuminationist
neoplatonism
The ontological counterpart of Suhraward¯ı’s critique of Peripatetic
epistemology is the doctrine of i‘tiba¯ ra¯ t ‘aqliyya or beings of
reason.23 I‘tiba¯ r means taking something into account or considering
something. Beings of reason for Suhraward¯ı are those concepts
that result from themind’s contemplation of the thing, not from the
apprehension of the concrete qualities of the thing. If we say that a
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Suhraward¯ı 211
particular horse has four legs or is brown, these are concrete qualities,
properties that we meet in the actual horse in the real world.
However, if we say that the horse is existent, one, or contingent,
these are properties that have to do with how we think about the
real horse. When properties are made into nouns, brownness and
four-leggedness refer to something concrete while existence, unity,
and contingency do not – or, if they do, they all refer to the same
thing, the horse itself.24
The target of this analysis is, as usual, the Peripatetics. Avicenna
had made a distinction between the essence – or, more properly,
quiddity – of a thing and its existence. He pointed out that you could
ask two quite different questions about a thing: “Is it?” and “What
is it?” The first addressed its existence and the second its quiddity.25
The Aristotelian roots of this distinction are obvious, and it is clearly
a useful clarification of Aristotle, employing the distinction between
the Arabic participle and infinitive. The distinction is legitimate.
The difficulty is that Avicenna seems to assume that a real distinction
corresponds to the mental distinction, that if we can distinguish
the existence from the quiddity of a thing, the thing must contain
both existence and quiddity. The move is the more natural since it
reflects an Aristotelian tendency to explain things as combinations
of substrates and forms. There are difficulties. Bemused European
philosophers pointed out that the distinction implied that existence
was an accident.26 The problem, as Suhraward¯ı relentlessly points
out, is that it leads to insuperable problems of regression. One can
ask the same questions about the quiddity and the existence. Is there
a quiddity and existence of the existence and of the quiddity? What
about the existence of the existence of the existence? Similar arguments
can be made against the other beings of reason: unity, contingency,
necessity, and the like.
Suhraward¯ı gives a parallel critique of the Peripatetic doctrine of
hylomorphism, the theory that material bodies are compounds of
matter and form, with form being a composite of forms of different
kinds: species, accidents, elements, and qualities of various sorts.
Suhraward¯ı finds this all quite implausible and argues instead for
a simpler explanation, that bodies are just self-subsistent magnitude
and qualities. It is a theory that has its origins in Plato’s
Timaeus and reappears occasionally thereafter in the history of philosophy,
notably in Descartes. It is not particularly central to the
Illuminationist project, for the theory is abandoned by Suhraward¯ı’s
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
212 john walbridge
commentator Qut.b al-D¯ın Sh¯ır ¯az¯ı, but it is characteristic of Suhraward
¯ı’s ontologically parsimonious critique of the Peripatetics.27
In modern times, Suhraward¯ı is best known for the metaphysics
of light that appears in the second book of The Philosophy of Illumination.
The relation of this system to the critique of the Peripatetics
in the first half of that book is reasonably clear: the Peripatetic
doctrines that he refutes concern the fundamental epistemological
and metaphysical issues where his new system differs from that of
Avicenna.28 It is less clear how the metaphysics of The Philosophy
of Illumination relates to his so-called Peripatetic works, some of
which were written at roughly the same time as this work. The usual
account is that these other works are intended for those incapable
of understanding the true Illuminationist philosophy and are therefore
of at best limited significance for understanding Suhraward¯ı’s
thought. I aminclined to doubt it, since his later followers seem to
have made no such distinction, but the solution waits on serious
study of Suhraward¯ı’s other philosophical works.
Whatever may be the relation of the second part of The Philosophy
of Illumination to his other work, its philosophical doctrine
is reasonably clear with careful reading and the advice of the early
commentators.29 Suhraward¯ı begins by identifying his fundamental
concepts: light and darkness, independent and dependent. Light, he
explains, is the most self-evident of entities, “that which is manifest
in itself and manifests others,” says one of the commentators, citing
a well-known definition of light.30 The independent entity is that
whose existence or perfections do not rest upon another. Darkness
and the dependent are the opposite. Moreover, light and darkness can
be either self-subsistent or in another. This corresponds to a distinction
that he made earlier between substance, that whose existence
is not diffused throughout another, and states, which exist diffused
throughout another. These distinctions yield four classes of entities:
(1) Self-subsistent or immaterial lights, which the commentators
identify with intellects.
(2) Barriers or substantial darknesses, which are bodies.
(3) Accidental lights, which are physical light and various other
self-manifesting accidents.
(4)Dark accidents, those properties that are not manifest in
themselves.
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Suhraward¯ı 213
Everything that exists falls into one of these four classes. Light is
active; darkness, whether substantial or accidental, is passive.
(1) Immaterial lights are intellects orminds. The key concept here
is “self-evident” or “manifest.” Immaterial lights are manifest both
to other things, like all light, and to themselves, which is to say
that they are self-aware and aware of other things. Therefore, anything
that is alive must be an immaterial light. They are, we must be
clear, lights, not light. Suhraward¯ı is not thinking of a substratum of
luminous matter or chunks of light that are emitted from something
luminous, cross the intervening space, and fall on something else. He
is thinking of distinct luminous individual incorporeal things whose
essence is tobemanifest. They are more likeLeibnizian monads than
like the undifferentiated primal reality of existence that we find in
some later philosophers like Mull¯a S. adr¯a and Sabziw¯ar¯ı. They are
individualized by differences in intensity and by luminous and dark
accidents; Suhraward¯ı has earlier argued that things can differ by the
intensity of their being. If they are above a certain level of intensity,
their ability to manifest other things includes the ability to bring
other things into being and to sustain their existence. His concept
of immaterial light can be identified with the ordinary Peripatetic
concept of intellect but with two new features: first, if immaterial
lights are sufficiently intense, they can create, and, second, they are
manifest to other immaterial lights, so that we can, in principle, see
God and the celestial intellects/lights. (2) Dark barriers or bodies are
more or less the opposite. They are neither manifest in themselves,
nor do they manifest another. Therefore, they can be seen only with
the aid of accidental light and be known only by incorporeal lights,
and they are alive only insofar as they are associated with an incorporeal
light. They are passive, not active, so that both their activities
and they themselves are the effects of lights. (3) Accidental lights are
physical lights and the luminous accidents that occur in both barriers
and in immaterial lights. Like immaterial lights, accidental lights are
manifest and manifest other things, but since they subsist in something
else, they are not self-aware or alive. (4) Dark accidents are the
qualities of physical things that are not manifest in themselves, as
well as certain states in immaterial lights.
All these entities are connected through illumination and their
presence to each other. The immaterial lights must be causally primary,
since an accident in itself cannot be the cause of a substance
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
214 john walbridge
nor can a passive darkness be the cause of light with its activity. The
more intense immaterial lights can be the efficient and sustaining
causes of other immaterial lights less intense than themselves. They
can also be the cause of both luminous and dark accidents in lower
lights due to the lower light’s contemplation respectively of the luminosity
of the higher light and its own relation of dependence. Thus,
immaterial lights can differ in intensity and in luminous and dark
accidents. Finally, the immaterial lights can be the cause of barriers,
bodies, through their aspect of dependence on another. The immaterial
lights are also the ultimate cause of the luminous accidents
in physical bodies – which is to say, physical light – as well as their
dark accidents. If we work our way up this causal chain of entities
we reach first immaterial lights and finally an immaterial light that
is not caused by another immaterial light, the Light of Lights or God.
From this set of entities and relationships, Suhraward¯ı derives his
cosmology. First – in an ontological, not a temporal sense – there is
the Light of Lights. Its illumination results in another immaterial
light, and this second light’s illumination results in a third immaterial
light. Suhraward¯ı calls this the vertical order of lights. At some
point, there is a double effect, both an immaterial light resulting
from the luminosity of the higher light and a material sphere resulting
from its dependence on and separation from the Light of Lights.
This is the outer sphere of the universe. At each step down from here,
there is another immaterial light and another sphere. At some point,
there also begin to be material lights associated with the spheres.
Moreover, immaterial lights begin to multiply on the lower levels
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |