9
revolutionary word. It has been stolen by those who would rule over the people, to add
legitimacy to their rule. While there may well be forms of representation or delegation that are
compatible with democracy, to reduce democracy to a justification for some to rule over others is
to abandon the notion that “the people” might actually “rule” themselves.
Though elections may
be democratic, they are not the same as democracy. Many of the Egyptian revolutionaries, who I
think were clearly motivated by the democratic ideal, opposed early elections in their country
because they knew they would be manipulated by the main powerhouses in the country: the
Army and the Muslim Brotherhood (and they were right). I – and, based on the survey data
noted above, I suspect many of my fellow citizens, too – have wondered if a similar dynamic is
in play in the U.S. context: elections are controlled by powerful elites. Wolin (2008, 47), for
example, has argued that the U.S. should be regarded not as a “full” or “consolidated”
democracy, but rather as a “‘managed democracy,’ a political form in which governments are
legitimated by elections they have learned to control.” Fundamentally, I reject justificatory
invocation
of democracy, because democracy’s function is not to legitimate rulers, but to enable
self-rule. Democracy’s task is not to authorize some to govern others, but to authorize all of us
to govern ourselves.
Radical Democracy: Democracy as an Ideal
Third, democracy is conceptualized as a radical ideal. I mean radical in two distinct, but
related, senses: 1) going to the root meaning of a concept, and 2) as advocating fundamental
change. In the first place, to advocate for radical democracy entails an effort to recover and
reaffirm the root meaning of the word. Democracy is the conjoining of
demos
(people) with
kratia
(power or rule).
Standard definitions slip away from this primary idea. The
Oxford English
Dictionary
tells us that democracy means “government by the people”…The
10
trouble starts…when ‘power’ is replaced by ‘government.’ If ‘government’ means
governance – the process of governing – then it means about the same as power,
and there is no difficulty. But if it means ‘a government’ – the political
institutions existing in a society – then we have to an entirely different category of
proposition…What we have now is no longer a definition but a hypothesis. The
hypothesis is that the way to get power to the people is to put them in charge of
‘the government,’ that is, the state apparatus (Lummis 1996, 23).
Hence, democracy, at its core, means rule by the people, or a condition in which people have
power –
nothing more, nothing less
. As Lummis (
ibid
. 22) puts it:
[D]emocracy is not the name of any particular arrangement of political or
economic institutions. Rather, it is a situation
that political or economic
institutions may or may not help to bring about. It describes an ideal, not a
method for achieving it. It is not a kind of government, but an end of
government; not a historically existing institution, but historical project.
At its core, then, democracy is about people having political power. More than that, it is
premised on the notion of political equality, that people have roughly equal power to shape
common affairs. And, to say that people share power, or share in
ruling themselves is, to use
Arendt’s language in describing the ancient Athenian polis, fundamentally a situation in which
there is, in fact, “no-rule, without a division between rulers and ruled” (Arendt 1963, 20). Rather
than being ruled, democracy entails people ruling themselves. Rather than authorizing someone
else’s power, democracy occurs when people mobilize their own power. Rather than being
governed, democracy is about governing ourselves. Democracy as a radical ideal, therefore, is
about self-governance, and entails a vision of a truly free and egalitarian
political order to be
perpetually strived for, if never fully achieved.
I do not just mean radical in the etymological sense, however, but also in the political
sense. Here, radical is juxtaposed to reform. While the reformist wishes to change certain
policies or tinker around the edges, the radical wishes to change the basic structure of society –
its basic organization of power and patterns of ownership. Hence, the “radical” in radical
11
democracy means not only holding tight to democracy’s root meaning, but also viewing it as
something that is politically radically, in the sense of being subversive of, and seeking to
transform, all society’s basic power structure. Indeed, the former implies the latter. If
democracy means a situation in which people have power, then democracy is subversive of any
situation in which power is concentrated away from people rather than dispersed among them.
“[R]adical democracy is subversive everywhere. It is subversive not
only in military
dictatorships but also in countries that are called democratic…It is subversive not only inside big
corporations but also inside big unions” (Lummis 1996, 25). Perhaps the most concentrated
form of power in the world is the modern state. Following Weber, I define the state as the entity
in society (or a territory) that possesses a monopoly on the legitimate use of violence. It is safe
to say that such an entity – all the more so given modern technologies of surveillance and
violence – possesses enormous coercive power. From my perspective, then, I see radical
democracy as, at a minimum, in tension with the state and, perhaps, as essentially incompatible
with the state. It is worth pausing for a moment to appreciate
how divergent this
conceptualization of democracy is from the prior two. Whereas the institutional approach
defines
democracy as a set of state institutions and justificatory approach views democracy as a
way of
legitimating
state institutions, the radical approach sees the democratic state as, in a
sense, an oxymoron. Radical democracy is something that occurs outside of, and often in
opposition to, the democratic state.
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: