210
hostile to the council system than the conservative or reactionary right” (
ibid
.
239).
For these reasons, I am inclined to suggest that the relationship between radical democracy and
the state is not just one of tension, but rather one of opposition. They are irreconcilable social
forms: “the multitude” rather than “the people,” “non-sovereign nodes” rather than the
“sovereign body,” “centrifugal power” rather than “centripetal power.”
I say this knowing full
well that the radical democracy I have outlined – built on the practices of direct action and
networked organization – is not a “complete” political proposal. It is not my intention, nor do I
claim, to have presented a model of social organization that resolves all, or even most, of our
basic political questions. Rather my aim has been to restore and reaffirm democracy’s radical
nature, to position it as a revolutionary project, and to elaborate some of its core commitments
(e.g.
non-domination, non-sovereignty, self-governance, and diversity) and practices (direct
action and networked organization).
Independent of the questions of the feasibility or desirability of a revolution premised on
these commitments and practices, I want to conclude by posing the question: What would
radically democratic revolution even mean? To be sure:
Twentieth century history is full of births of worlds that embody ‘old’ social
relations…[I]n general, revolutions have not given birth to new worlds, though
revolutionaries have tried to build them with the state apparatus…Despite the
unimpeachable goodwill of so many revolutionaries, the
fact remains that the state
is not the appropriate tool for creating emancipatory social relations” (Zibechi
2010, 4).
What would it mean to do things differently and truly along radically democratic lines? If
radical democracy means the dispersion of power, then a radically democratic revolution must
not only mobilize power against the state, but also check the very power it generates. The
challenge of such a revolution is to
build
power, but not
take
power.
211
My hunch is that cultivating practices of direct action and networked organization have
the potential to balance these two objectives. On the one hand, direct action mobilizes collective
power and networks can function to amplify that power. On the other hand,
democratic
direct
action undercuts power inequalities and opens up spaces for others to exercise political power.
Additionally, networked organization “…is based on the continuing plurality of its elements…in
such a way that reduction to a centralized and unified command structure is impossible” (Hardt
and Negri 2004, 82-83).
In these ways, direct action and networks have the capacity to build
power without taking power. Indeed, a peculiarity about the power that is generated by social
movements is that it has a self-limiting quality. As Arendt (1963, 166) puts it, “power comes
into being only if and when men (
sic
) join themselves together for the purpose of action and it
will disappear when, for whatever reason, they disperse and desert one another.” To its credit,
this form of power can only be sustained so long as it is generated and propelled forward by
collective action. Beyond that, I would argue that radical democrats have responsibility to
cultivate limitations on the very power they develop. This means a self-conscious effort to leave
room
for other people, and other nodes of power. Consider this point from an internal debate
about the direction of the “Dissent! Network” in the U.K:
Whatever Dissent! is, it is not THE network of resistance, we shouldn’t be trying
to involve everyone possible, or we monopolise everything. I don’t see Dissent!
as some kind of revolutionary council. We should get back to what we already
are, a network” (quoted in Maeckelbergh 2009, 112).
The argument here is that while Dissent! is rightly mobilizing collective power against state and
capital, it also must put limits on itself. It should not attempt to be the sole network. The goal is
not
to have everyone join their group or to have their organization involved in every struggle.
This would be tantamount to an effort to create a single locus of power against state and capital,
and
if they were successful, the origins of a new state.
212
Thus, the paradoxical situation for the theory and practice of radical democracy is how to
generate power against domination, without recreating new forms of domination. A major aim
of this dissertation is to provide some insights from anti-authoritarian theorists and social
movements that speak to this possibility. Nonetheless, a radically democratic revolution faces
two seemingly insurmountable challenges
simultaneously
: it must overthrow the most powerful
states that have ever existed, and prevent the rise of new states from developing internally. This
is not advantageous
terrain from which to fight, but these are the terms of the struggle for radical
democracy.
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: