Beyond the democratic state: anti-authoritarian interventions in democratic theory



Download 0,97 Mb.
Pdf ko'rish
bet75/83
Sana27.06.2022
Hajmi0,97 Mb.
#707978
1   ...   71   72   73   74   75   76   77   78   ...   83
Bog'liq
beyondTheDemocraticStateAntiAuthoritarianInterventionsIn

without requiring
:
1)
Clearly defined boundaries
around the ‘polity,’ since people within a specific geographic 
location might not be included in a network, while those outside a geographic location 
may be included. As Maeckelbergh (2009, 188-89) puts it: “A decentralized network has 
no start, no end and certainly no geographical boundaries fixed over time...Consequently, 
‘the people’ in a decentralized democratic praxis are constituted by the links they make 
with each other…”
2)
Elections, 
since “the people” is in no way fixed and their boundaries are always unclear 
and constantly shifting. Thus, there is no way to allow everyone to vote. Indeed, the 
very concept of elections with universal suffrage becomes unintelligible in this context.
3)
A centralized decision-making body
, since all a single actor can do is issue proposals or 
lead by example, but cannot require that (or how) other actors engage with these. 
4)
A single, unifying and binding decision
, since each actor in the network is able to choose 
if (or how) to participate, and the final outcomes that the network produces is the result of 
the numerous and diverse decisions of the actors in the network. 


199 
The theory of network democracy elaborated in this chapter pushes at the boundaries of what we 
think of as constituting democracy. However, it is precisely by upsetting these most basic 
assumptions that radical democracy remains possible today. 
 
 
 
 
 
 


200 
CONCLUSION 
 
DEMOCRACY AS THE DISPERSION OF POWER 
I. From Legitimation to Dispersion 
Some of the central questions of political theory center on the issue of legitimacy. What 
gives some the right to rule over others? What authorizes the use of political power and 
coercion? Why is the state – whether it takes the form of monarchy, or oligarchy, or aristocracy, 
or democracy – legitimate? Though the anti-authoritarian account of democracy I have 
presented in the preceding chapters is not a statist account of democracy, it nonetheless involves 
the mobilization of political power. Indeed, this was precisely the point: democracy means 
situations in which people have power and, thus, practices like direct action ought to be 
considered as having radically democratic potential. However, in making the argument that 
direct action has democratic potential, I naturally invite questions about legitimacy. The 
disruptive power of direct action interrupts or halts existing institutional processes: blocking 
roads, attacking property, stopping commerce. The prefigurative power of direct action 
addresses perceived problems, constructs new relationships, and/or builds new institutions, 
without going through formal processes of official authorization. In both instances, the 
mobilization of political power has consequences – often coercive consequences – for other 
members of society. As such, direct action raises problems of legitimacy: if direct action is 
fundamentally a form of political power, then what legitimates this exercise of power? Hardt 
and Negri (2004, 79-80) pose the question this way: 
It is possible today to imagine a new process of legitimation that does not rely on 
the sovereignty of the people [since neither the practice of direct action, nor their 
concept of “the multitude” makes claims to sovereignty]…Is there an immanent 
mechanism that does not appeal to any transcendent authority that is capable of 
legitimating the use of force in the multitude’s struggle to create a new society 
based on democracy, equality, and freedom? 


201 
I do not think Hardt and Negri ever quite get around to answering this most challenging question.
In Chapter III, I aimed to provide some criteria for assessing the democratic legitimacy of direct 
actions – criteria that I take to be “immanent” to the democratic ideal itself. For example, direct 
actions are democratic when a) they upset power inequalities and make real the political equality 
on which democracy depends, and b) open up or create spaces for others to exercise political 
freedom. To the extent that direct actions do both, I see them as a legitimate mobilization of 
power or force. However, I do not pretend that such tentative criteria resolve the myriad 
legitimacy issues that the practice of direct action generates.
The legitimacy questions are all the more challenging because direct actions always 
involve only some small part of the 
demos
. They are, in Wolin’s (2008, 277) words, the 
“initiatives of a fraction, not a collective whole.” Even in the most renowned cases of popular 
democratic movements, only a fraction of “the people” was represented. During the American 
Revolution, no more than 50 percent of Americans actively supported the revolution and some 
15 to 20 percent were actively opposed (Calhoon 2004, 235). Similarly, Poland’s Solidarity 
Movement against Soviet rule mobilized, at most, a quarter of the population (Canovan 2005, 
136). And, in most cases, the participation rates in direct actions are significantly lower. This, 
of course, raises a problem: If direct action always involves only a 
fraction
of “the people,” does 
this practice then not fly in the face of the notion that 
all
of “the people” should rule? If 
democracy means, at its core, “rule by the people” or “a situation in which people have power,” 
and if direct action only enables 
some
people to have power, then is it really a radically 
democratic practice?
The basic thrust of the answer – and, I suspect, a major reason why Hardt and Negri do 
not directly respond the question they pose – is that an anti-authoritarian account of democracy 


202 
rejects political theory’s focus on legitimation. The basic goal of democratic theory from this 
perspective is not to 
legitimate
the 
centralization
of power, but instead to 
enable
its 
dispersion
.
The fundamental question for this type of democratic theory is not “How can power can be 
legitimated?” but instead, “How can power be dispersed?” This question involves a shift in 
focus. Rather than studying or promoting practices or procedures that legitimate sovereign 
power, we should theorize and cultivate practices and procedures that disperse non-sovereign 
power.

Download 0,97 Mb.

Do'stlaringiz bilan baham:
1   ...   71   72   73   74   75   76   77   78   ...   83




Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©hozir.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling

kiriting | ro'yxatdan o'tish
    Bosh sahifa
юртда тантана
Боғда битган
Бугун юртда
Эшитганлар жилманглар
Эшитмадим деманглар
битган бодомлар
Yangiariq tumani
qitish marakazi
Raqamli texnologiyalar
ilishida muhokamadan
tasdiqqa tavsiya
tavsiya etilgan
iqtisodiyot kafedrasi
steiermarkischen landesregierung
asarlaringizni yuboring
o'zingizning asarlaringizni
Iltimos faqat
faqat o'zingizning
steierm rkischen
landesregierung fachabteilung
rkischen landesregierung
hamshira loyihasi
loyihasi mavsum
faolyatining oqibatlari
asosiy adabiyotlar
fakulteti ahborot
ahborot havfsizligi
havfsizligi kafedrasi
fanidan bo’yicha
fakulteti iqtisodiyot
boshqaruv fakulteti
chiqarishda boshqaruv
ishlab chiqarishda
iqtisodiyot fakultet
multiservis tarmoqlari
fanidan asosiy
Uzbek fanidan
mavzulari potok
asosidagi multiservis
'aliyyil a'ziym
billahil 'aliyyil
illaa billahil
quvvata illaa
falah' deganida
Kompyuter savodxonligi
bo’yicha mustaqil
'alal falah'
Hayya 'alal
'alas soloh
Hayya 'alas
mavsum boyicha


yuklab olish