whose loyalty to Islam must either be based on some formof fideism
or must be disingenuous. Yet this dilemma and its dangerous horns
should be rejected for a more sympathetic understanding of Averroes
as a devotee of the most sophisticated and dominant religion of his
historical culture, Islam. A distinguished scholar and religious qa¯dı¯,
Averroes’ devotion to Islam and its religious practices was never significantly
questioned in a way prominent to historical scholarship.
Rather, it is apparent that Averroes held the world and its First Principle,
God, to be through and through rational in nature, such that
human rational endeavors are understood to be the keys to the most
complete knowledge and happiness open to human beings.His philosophical
thought includes important roles for religion in the development
of human powers toward their fulfillment in the highest
intellectual insight into God and his creation, even as it gives critical
assessment to the truth and efficacy of religious arguments and
statements.
notes
1 Druart [141].
2 Averroes, Taha¯ fut al-taha¯ fut, ed. M. Bouyges, S.J. (Beirut: 1930), 427–8;
Averroes [140], 257–8.
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
198 richard c. taylor
3 See G. Endress, “Averrois Opera: A Bibliography of Editions and Contributions
to the Text,” in Aertsen and Endress [134], 339–81.
4 See C. Burnett, “The Second Revelation of Arabic Philosophy and
Science: 1492–1562,” in C. Burnett and A. Contadini (eds.), Islam and
the Italian Renaissance (London: 1999), 185–98.
5 See E. Renan, Averro`es et l’averro¨ısme, in OEuvres compl`etes de Ernest
Renan, ed. H. Psichari, vol. III (Paris: 1852); A. von Ku‥ glegen, Averroes
und die arabische Moderne: Ansa¨ tze zu einer Neubegru¨ ndung des
Rationalismus im Islam (Leiden:1994). Also see von Ku‥ glegen, “A
Call for Rationalism: ‘Arab Averroists’ in the Twentieth Century,” Alif
(Cairo) 16 (1996), 97–132.
6 See O. Leaman, Averroes and his Philosophy (Oxford: 1988) and O.
Leaman, A Brief Introduction to Islamic Philosophy (Oxford: 1999).
7 Averroes, Taha¯ fut, 427–8; Averroes [140], 257–8. Translation slightly
modified; Arabic added.
8 Averroes, Sharh. al-burh¯ an li-Arist.
u¯ , in A. Badawı¯ (ed.), Ibn Rushd,
Sharh. al-burh¯ an li-Arist.
¯ u wa-talkh¯ıs.
al-burha¯n (Grand Commentaire
et Paraphrase des “Secondes Analytiques” d’Aristote) (Kuwait: 1984),
184; Latin In Aristotelis Opera Cum Averrois Commentariis (Venice:
1562; repr. Frankfurt a.M.: 1962), vol. I, pt. 2, bk. 1, Comment 9, 32rA.
At 32vD Averroes quotes Aristotle’s text that true conclusions can be
made from false premises, though those conclusions are per accidens.
The next Comment argues that the conditions for demonstration must
be met completely.
9 In this translation I follow A. El Ghannouchi, “Distinction et relation
des discours philosophique et religieux chez Ibn Rushd: Fasl al
maqal ou la double v’erit ’ e,” in Averroes (1126–1198) oder der Triumph
des Rationalismus: Internationales Symposium anla¨ sslich des 800.
Todestages des islamischen Philosophen, ed. R. G. Khoury (Heidelberg:
2002), 139–45; see 145.
10 See chapter 4 above; and al-F ¯ar¯ab¯ı, Tah.
s.
ı¯l al-sa‘a¯da, in Rasa¯ ’il al-Fa¯ ra¯bı¯
(Hyderabad: 1926/1345 A. H.), 29–36; “The Attainment of Happiness,”
in Alfarabi’s Philosophy of Plato and Aristotle, trans.M. Mahdi (Ithaca,
NY: 1969), sect. iii, 34–41. Cf. Walzer [77], ch. 17, 276–85.
11 Averroes [139], 49. Translation slightly modified.
12 For detailed discussion of this rendering of Aristotle, Prior Analytics,
I.32, 47a8–9, see Taylor [148].
13 Averroes [139], 51.
14 Averroes, Taha¯ fut, 151–2; Averroes [140], 90. Creation ex nihilo is
also denied in the Long Commentary on the “Metaphysics”: Averroes,
Tafsı¯r ma¯ ba‘d al-t.abı¯‘a, ed. M. Bouyges (Beirut: 1949), 1497–1505;
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Averroes 199
Engl. trans. at Averroes [137], 108–12; Latin in In Aristotelis Opera
cum Averrois Commentariis, vol. VIII, 304rD–305vI.
15 Averroes [139], 57.
16 Averroes, Taha¯ fut, 582; Averroes [140], 360.
17 Averroes [139], 75.
18 Ibid.
19 Ibid.
20 Averroes [139], 61.
21 Taylor [216].
22 Ibn Rushd (Averroes), al-Kashf ‘an al-mana¯hij al-adilla fı¯ ‘aqa¯ ’id almilla
(Beirut: 1998), 118–19; English trans. Averroes [136], 79ff.
23 See M. Geoffroy, “L’Almohadisme th’eologique d’Averro`es (Ibn
Rushd),” Archives d’histoire doctrinale et litte´ raire du moyen aˆ ge 66
(1999), 9–47.
24 Averroes [135], 433.Mytranslation. For other texts, see S. Harvey, “The
Quiddity of Philosophy according toAverroes and Falaquera:AMuslim
Philosopher and his Jewish Interpreter,” in J. A. Aertsen and A. Speer
(eds.), Was ist Philosophie imMittelalter? (Berlin: 1998), 904–13. Also
see Taylor [146].
25 Ibn Rushd (Averroes), Middle Commentary on Aristotle’s “Prior Analytics”
(Arabic), ed. M. M. Kassem, with C. E. Butterworth and A. Abd
al-Magid Haridi (Cairo: 1983), 226.
26 These are (1) the Epistle on the Possibility of Conjunction, trans. K. P.
Bland (New York: 1982); (2) Epistle #1 On Conjunction and (3) Epistle
#2 On Conjunction, ed. and trans. in M. Geoffroy and C. Steel (eds.),
Averroe`s, La be´atitude de l’aˆme: e´ditions, traductions et e´ tudes (Paris:
2001); (4) De Separatione Primi Principii, inC. Steel andG. Guldentops,
“An Unknown Treatise of Averroes against the Avicennians on the
First Cause: Edition and Translation,” Recherches de th´eologie et
philosophiem´edi ´evales 64 (1997), 86–135; and (5) the Commentary on
the “De Intellectu” of Alexander, in M. Zonta, “La tradizione guideoaraba
ed ebraica del De intellectu di Alessandro di Afrodisa e il testo
originale del Commento di Averro` e,” Annali di Ca’ Foscari 40.3 (2001),
17–35.
27 Epitome de Anima (Arabic text), ed. S. G’omez Nogales (Madrid: 1985),
108. G’omez Nogales has also translated his edition as La psicolog´ıa
de Averroes: comentario al libro sobre el alma de Aristo´ teles (Madrid:
1987).
28 Epitome de Anima, 124.
29 Averroes [138], 111–12.
30 Averroes [135], 387. The account which follows is based on 387–8.
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
200 richard c. taylor
31 Averroes [135], 409.
32 Averroes [135], 411–12.
33 Averroes [135], 439.
34 “[W]ithout the imaginative power and the cogitative [power] the intellect
which is called material understands nothing” (Averroes [135],
450).
35 “[T]hat in virtue of which something carries out its proper activity is
the form, while we carry out our proper activity in virtue of the agent
intellect, it is necessary that the agent intellect be forminus” (Averroes
[135], 500). Also see 439. On “our final form,” see 444–5, 485–6, 490.
36 In the Long Commentary on the “Metaphysics”: Averroes, Tafsı¯r ma¯
ba‘d al-t.ab¯ı‘a, 1599.7.
37 See Davidson [208], 220ff.
38 Averroes, Tafsı¯r ma¯ ba‘d al-t.abı¯‘a, 313ff.; see also 1279ff.
39 See C. Baz’an, “Was There Ever a ‘First Averroism’?” in Miscellanea
Mediaevalia 27 (Berlin: 2000), 31–53.
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
john walbridge
10 Suhraward¯ı and Illuminationism
suhraward ̄ı and his career
One is tempted to romanticize Suhraward¯ı.1 Indeed, there is no particular
reason to avoid romanticizing himas a personality. He lived the
life of a wanderingwise man, and his story involved a prince, a magic
gem, the fabulous Saladin, and a tragic early death.We can see himas
his contemporaries saw him – probably as he saw himself – as a figure
out of philosophical folklore, the like of whom had not been seen
since Apollonius of Tyana. However, in my view it is a grave error
to examine his philosophy, Illuminationism, through romantic spectacles,
for Suhraward¯ı, despite his own attempts to mystify his project,
was a hardheaded philosophical critic and creative thinker who
set the agenda for later Islamic philosophy. Al-Ghaz¯ al¯ı’s attempt to
make religion independent of reason and Averroes’ Aristotelianism
left little trace in later Islamic thought, but Suhraward¯ı’s critique of
Avicenna’s ontology and of Aristotelian epistemology and his solutions
to these problems were his successors’ starting points. The
modern description of his philosophy as “theosophy” does not do
justice to the rigor and philosophical influence of his thought.2
Suhraward¯ı was probably born around 1154 in the village of
Suhraward near Zanj ¯an in northwestern Iran.3 We know nothing
of his family or ethnic background. He first appears in Mar¯agha, a
nearby city, where he studied logic and philosophy with Majd al-D¯ın
al-J¯ıl¯ı, a scholar of moderate prominence who also was the teacher
of the famous theologian Fakhr al-D¯ın al-R¯az¯ı. Later he studied with
Fakhr al-D¯ın al-M¯ard¯ın¯ı, either in M¯ard¯ın in southeastern Anatolia
or in Isfahan. M¯ard¯ın¯ı was a prominent teacher of medicine and the
rational sciences and apparently a S.
u¯ fı¯. In Isfahan he studied Ibn
201
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
202 john walbridge
Sahla¯n al-Sa¯wı¯’s Bas.a¯ ’ir, an innovative text on logic, with the otherwise
unknown Zah¯ır al-F ¯aris¯ı (or al-Q¯ar¯ı). He seems to have spent
his twenties wandering in central Anatolia and northern Syria in
search of patronage. His books written in this period are dedicated
to various local dignitaries.
At some point in these wanderings Suhraward¯ı abandoned the
Avicennian Peripatetic philosophy that he had learned from his
teacher and became a Platonist. It was, he tells us, his mystical exercises
and a dream of Aristotle that led to his conversion. He does not
explain in detail the mystical experiences, though they seem to have
been connected with the apprehension of the Platonic Forms.4 As for
the dream, Aristotle appeared to him one night, shining with light.
Suhraward¯ı had been struggling with the problem of knowledge.
Aristotle explained that the key to understanding knowledge was
self-consciousness – the basis of the doctrine of knowledge by presence,
of which I will say more presently. After he had finished his
explanations, Aristotle began praising Plato. Startled by the extravagence
of the praise, Suhraward¯ı asked Aristotle whether any of
the Islamic philosophers had reached that rank. It was only the
ecstatic mystics like Bist. ¯am¯ı and Tustar¯ı who were worthy of the
great philosopher’s notice.5
In 1183 he came to Aleppo, which had just been captured by
Saladin. It is said that he entered the city in clothes so shabby that he
wasmistaken for a donkey driver. He took up residence at amadrasa,
where the director quickly realized that he was a man of learning and
tactfully sent his young son with a gift of decent clothes. Suhraward¯ı
brought out a large gem and told the boy to go to the market and have
it priced. The boy came back and reported that the prince-governor,
a teenaged son of Saladin, had bid 30,000 dirhams for it. Suhraward¯ı
then smashed the gem with a rock, telling the boy that he could
have had better clothes had he wished.6 Suhraward¯ı was soon under
the protection of the prince. He finished his most important work,
The Philosophy of Illumination, three years later on September 15,
1186, on an evening when the sun, the moon, and the five Ptolemaic
planets were all in conjunction in Libra.7
Suhraward¯ı’s ascendancy over the prince, al-Malik al-Z. ¯ahir,
aroused the jealousy of various local scholars. The magical powers
and mystical attainments that he is said to have flaunted cannot
have helped relations. Complaints reached the ear of Saladin.
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Suhraward¯ı 203
Suhraward¯ı’s philosophy would have sounded like Ism¯a‘¯ılism to
Saladin and his conservative religious advisors, and Aleppo was of
great strategic importance, especially with the looming threat of the
Third Crusade. Accordingly, Saladin ordered Suhraward¯ı’s execution,
and the young prince reluctantly acceded. Suhraward¯ı probably died
in 1191, though the accounts are contradictory.8 The circle of disciples
who had accompanied him scattered, and not even their names
are recorded.
suhraward ̄ı’s writings and the transition from
peripatetic to illuminationist philosophy
There is a major difficulty in interpreting Suhraward¯ı’s thought. He
is known as Shaykh al-Ishra¯q, which means – we will tentatively
(and tendentiously) say – “the master of illumination” or, less dramatically,
“the founder of the Illuminationist school.” The question
is, what might that mean? In the introduction to The Philosophy of
Illumination Suhraward¯ı says:
Before I wrote this book and during the times when interruptions prevented
me from working on it, I wrote other books in which I have summarized
for you the principles of the Peripatetics according to their method . . .
I also have composed other works, some in my youth. But the present work
has another method and a shorter path to knowledge than their method. It
is more orderly and precise, less painful to study. I did not first arrive at
it through cogitation, but rather it was acquired through something else.
Subsequently I sought proof for it so that should I cease contemplating the
proof, nothing would make me fall into doubt.9
Combining this statement with what we know about Suhraward¯ı’s
surviving works, we can divide them into four classes:
(1) juvenilia;
(2) mystical works, notably a number of allegories;
(3) works expounding the principles of the Peripatetics according
to their methods;
(4) The Philosophy of Illumination.
Probably half or less of the bulk of Suhraward¯ı’s writings has been
published and only The Philosophy of Illumination and the allegories
have received serious scholarly attention, so anything we can
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
204 john walbridge
say about his works as a whole is necessarily tentative. So far,
Suhraward¯ı’s statement about his works has been understood in two
quite different ways.
The approach popularized by the late Henry Corbin, the scholar
most responsible for bringing Suhraward¯ı to the attention of world
scholarship, focuses on the mystical and mythical elements of
Suhraward¯ı’s thought. The “Peripatetic” works are simply an exercise
for those unable to pursue serious mystical – or to use the term
popularized by Corbin, “theosophical” – investigations. Therefore,
the works of Suhraward¯ı worthy of serious attention are the mystical
allegories and The Philosophy of Illumination less its first book,
which deals with logic and the critique of the Peripatetics. By this
account, Suhraward¯ı was a reviver of the wisdom of the ancient
Persians, as indicated by his use of light and darkness as fundamental
philosophical concepts and by his invocation of various Zoroastrian
sages and gods. Thus, Corbin translated the title of The Philosophy of
Illumination as “Le livre de th’eosophie orientale” and spent a good
deal of time talking about the importance of “spiritual geography”
in Suhraward¯ı’s thought.10
This was not how Suhraward¯ı was understood by most of his
successors in the Islamic world. For both followers like Qut.b al-
D¯ın al-Sh¯ır ¯az¯ı and critics like Mull¯a S. adr¯ a, he was a philosopher
who had made certain specific contributions in metaphysics, ontology,
and epistemology. Suhraward¯ı had begun with a critique of the
standard philosophy of the day, the Peripatetic system of Avicenna,
and attacked it on several major points. First, while attempting to
clarify the murky Aristotelian conception of being, Avicenna had
made a distinction between essence and existence and then assumed
that a real distinction must correspond to this mental distinction.
Suhraward¯ı attacked this assumption, arguing that conceptions such
as existencewere i‘tiba¯ rı¯, products of themind. Suhrawardı¯’s successors
accepted his critique ofAvicenna, but disagreed as to whether his
solution was adequate. Mull¯a S. adr¯ a, for example, held that in fact it
was essence, the differences among things, that was i‘tiba¯ rı¯. Second,
Suhraward¯ı criticized Avicenna’s Aristotelian conception of knowledge
by abstraction of forms. Instead, he argued that knowledge was
essentially the unmediated presence of the thing known to the conscious
knower. This theory was the basis of his use of mysticism
as a philosophical tool. This criticism and solution was generally
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Suhraward¯ı 205
accepted by his successors. Finally, Suhraward¯ı argued that philosophical
cosmology required the assumption that existents could differ
in intensity as well as in kind. Again, this theory was immensely
influential among his successors.
Suhraward¯ı made various other criticisms of the prevailing
Avicennian Peripateticism: a reassertion of the doctrine of Platonic
Forms, an attack on the Peripatetic theory of essential definition,
and an attack on the Peripatetic theory of matter, for example.
These were obviously philosophical positions, understood as such by
Suhraward¯ı’s successors. Moreover, The Philosophy of Illumination,
by universal agreement the most important of Suhraward¯ı’s works,
was understood by his successors through a series of philosophically
oriented commentaries, notably the commentary of Shahrazu¯ rı¯, its
adaptation by Qut.b al-D¯ın al-Sh¯ır ¯az¯ı, and the annotations by Mull¯a
S.
adr¯a. These commentaries translated its novel philosophical terminology
into the standard philosophical language of Avicenna so
that, for example, “barrier” becomes “body” and “managing light”
becomes “soul.”11 The legitimacy of this procedure was not, so far as
I know, questioned from within the Islamic philosophical tradition,
though it has been by some modern scholars.
Whether or not they were correct to label Suhraward¯ı a
“theosophist,” Corbin and his followers were quite correct in stressing
the importance of the passages in Surhaward¯ı’s writing concerning
his philosophical genealogy. Suhraward¯ı clearly saw himself
as the reviver of the most ancient tradition of philosophy. Modern
scholars for the most part would see the genealogy of Islamic philosophy
as going back to Aristotle as understood by his later commentators
with some Neoplatonic influence through stray texts like
the Theology of Aristotle. There was perhaps some slight influence
from other Greek philosophical schools and from other nations in
politics and ethics. Later on, there was influence fromS.
u¯ fism, with
Suhraward¯ı being one of the important instances.
Suhraward¯ı saw things differently. There were three ancient
sources of philosophical thought: the Egyptians, the Indians and
Chinese, and the ancient Persians. Themainstream of Islamic philosophy
derived ultimately from Egypt, from the philosopher-prophet
Hermes Trismegistus, also called Enoch or Idr¯ıs.12 Empedocles had
studied in Syria and Pythagoras in Egypt and Mesopotamia. The two
of them were the founders of the tradition of “divine philosophy” in
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
Cambridge Companions Online © Cambridge University Press, 2006
206 john walbridge
Greek philosophy. Socrates and Plato were under their influence,
and Aristotle was, of course, the student of Plato. The followers of
Aristotle took his philosophy in two directions. The Aristotelians
best known in the Islamic world were those who pursued only the
superficial aspects of his thought. Their champion wasAvicenna, and
Suhraward¯ı himself had belonged to their school. However, there
were also Aristotelians – including Aristotle himself in his later
years – who carried on the divine philosophy of Plato, which is represented
in such works as the Theology. In the meantime, there was
also a Pythagorean tradition that survived in Egypt and was associated
with the alchemists of Panopolis. Its Islamic representatives
were the S.
¯ uf¯ı alchemist Dh ¯ u al-N¯ un al-Mis.
r¯ı and his student Sahl
al-Tustar¯ı. Second, there was the tradition of the ancient Persians,
represented by various pre-Islamic Persian sages and by the ecstatic
PersianS.
u¯ fı¯s Abu¯ Yazı¯d al-Bast.a¯mı¯, al-H. alla¯ j, and al-Kharaqa¯nı¯. The
exact position of the Chinese and Indians, the third source of philosophy,
is less clear. Probably, Suhraward¯ı saw them mostly as having
parallel traditions of wisdom whose influence on Islamic philosophy,
such as it might be, was either through the Iranians or through
Pythagoras, who was thought to have journeyed in the East and to
have had followers in India. Suhraward¯ı was thus the first of the
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |