* This chapter has benefited from discussing many of the issues raised with Hrafn Asgeirsson,
Triantafyllos Gkouvas, Joanna Kyriakakis and Dale Smith; from comments provided by Lulu
audience members at the International Association for Constitutional Law Roundtable (Mel-
bourne Law School, 2nd May 2016) and the Australian Society of Legal Philosophy Confer-
ence (Melbourne Law School, 23rd July 2016). This research was supported by the Australian
Government through the Australian Research Council awards DP1092523 and DP140102670.
The Centrality and Diversity of the Invisible Constitution
147
the promulgation by certain social institutions of certain texts.
2
On Dworkin’s
own account, the moral requirements in question
are those principles which,
in light of the demands that integrity imposes on the exercise of the coercive
power of the state, would best justify the promulgated texts (together with
other legal practices);
3
on Greenberg’s account, the moral requirements are
those which are caused by certain texts having been promulgated by legal
authorities (together with other practices of those authorities).
4
On either
account, it seems obvious that the legal meaning and force of any legal text –
including a constitution – will depend upon the social context surrounding
its promulgation. Furthermore, this context constitutes an ‘invisible’ element
of the constitution in two distinct senses: (1) it lies outside the text, and yet is
crucial in determining the legal significance of the promulgated text; (2) it is
not something that would typically be included in a catalogue of the legal
phenomena that occur within a society.
5
Nevertheless, in a recent paper Greenberg appears to downplay the poten-
tial gap, on his account, between the visible and
the invisible constituents
of law:
[T]he legislative enactment of a statute may often have roughly the net effect
of adding to the content of the law a norm that is more or less captured by
the linguistic content of the legislation. But, when it does so, the explanation
will be that the enactment of the statute changed the relevant circumstances,
2
The italicised phrase is an attempt to capture what is common to the conception of law pre-
sented by Ronald Dworkin,
Law’s Empire (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1986)
and by Mark Greenberg, ‘The Moral Impact Theory of Law’ (2014) 123 Yale Law Journal 1288.
See also the discussion in Mark Greenberg, ‘The standard picture and its discontents’, in
Leslie Green and Brian Leiter (eds.) Oxford Studies in Philosophy of Law (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2011), 56.
3
Dworkin, Supra note 1, 90–4, 410–13 (‘the law of a community on this account is the scheme
of rights and responsibilities that . . . license coercion because they flow from past [political]
decisions of the right sort’: 93); see also the discussion in Greenberg, ‘The Moral Impact
Theory’, Supra note 1, 1292–3, 1299–1303.
4
Greenberg, ‘The Moral Impact Theory’, Supra note 1, 1293, 1301–3.
5
The editors, in chapter 1, capture a similar sense of the invisible when they refer to ‘aspects of a
constitutional tradition that are sufficiently deep or outside the confines of what is understood
as constitutional within a given system, that they are often overlooked as elements of actual
constitutional practice’. Martin Krygier’s work on the rule of law has consistently articulated
the dependence of law’s significance upon extra-legal social phenomena: see e.g., ‘Transitional
Questions about the Rule of Law: Why, What and How?’ (2001) 28 East Central Europe/L’Eu-
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: