as genuine, implications should have to satisfy a test of ‘obviousness’. Ryan
134
Jeffrey Goldsworthy
a test for constitutional implicatures,
98
but is criticised by Larry Solum in this
book for doing so.
99
Solum points out that implicatures are not always obvi-
ous; sometimes ‘competent speakers would need to read carefully to
see the
implicature’.
100
Some linguists regard implicatures as ‘always somewhat uncer-
tain’, because the communicative principles can conflict with one another,
and because doubts can arise at any stage of the complex reasoning process
that is involved.
101
Other forms of contextual enrichment such as ellipses are
also debatable. For example, s. 92 of the Australian Constitution is clearly
elliptical, but there was much disagreement about how the ellipsis should be
filled.
102
On the other hand, to show that utterance meanings are shaped partly by
what I have just described as implicit assumptions, a test of obviousness may
be appropriate. As I have previously argued:
implicit assumptions are unstated, or even unnoticed, precisely because they
are obvious. If so, there can be no such thing as an implicit assumption that
does not comply with the obviousness test, and so the test is necessary.
103
For other kinds of inexplicit content, including implicatures, ‘we do not
require obviousness in everyday interpretation. We employ a process of rea-
soning in which speakers’ meanings are inferred from various kinds of evi-
dence, with varying degrees of strength, and we are willing to accept a higher
risk of error than are the courts in interpreting legal documents’.
104
Obviousness, then, is not normally required. But it is open to courts to be
more cautious. They may be especially wary of error because they are not
generally permitted to rewrite the laws they are charged with interpreting.
They might regard attributing a non-existent implication to a law to be worse
than failing to identify a genuine one through excessive caution. That would,
of course, be debatable, but they might consequently subject themselves to
98
Williams, Supra note 42, 544.
99
L. Solum Section
3.6.3
. See also H. Asgeirrson, ‘On the Possibility of Non-literal Legislative
Speech’, in A. Capone and F. Poggi (eds.),
Pragmatics and Law: Theoretical and Practical
Perspectives (Springer Verlag, 2017), 11 who disagrees with A. Marmor on this point.
100
Solum, Supra note 99.
101
C. Potts, ‘Presupposition and Implicature’, in S. Lappin and C. Fox (eds.),
The Handbook of
Contemporary Semantic Theory, 2nd edn (Wiley Blackwell 2015), 168, 183.
102
See note 31.
103
Goldsworthy, chapter note, 170. Note also that Mason CJ in the
ACTV case did not require
‘textual’ implications to be ‘necessary’: see notes 120–122.
104
Goldsworthy, chapter note, 170. I did not at the time mention implicatures in this regard.