ment from an originalist perspective. After recognizing the legitimacy of con-
used in the provision and the relevant background context.
Further refinements may be required. The notion of a “reasonable member
“Remission or suspension of business or procedure; as, the house of representatives had a
that constitutional implications should be recognized if “the putatively implied content arises
as a matter of logical necessity due to a noncancellable, semantically encoded formulation.”
“for recognizing constitutional implicatures.” That characterization is inaccurate. The logical
consequences of semantic content are implications, not implicatures. See Kent Bach, “The
90
Lawrence B. Solum
on is not a legal question – it is a question about meaning. For this reason, we
might substitute “competent speaker of American English” for “reasonable
member.”
Williams uses the phrase “implied content,” but this usage runs the risk of
conflating implication with implicature, impliciture, and presupposition. We
might substitute “contextual enrichment.” Williams suggests that contextual
enrichment should be limited to content that is obvious and noncontroversial,
but it is not clear that this is the way that contextual enrichment always works.
Sometimes the communicative content of a text may not be “obvious” –
it may be that competent speakers would need to read carefully to see the
contextual enrichment. Likewise, the existence of controversy does not auto-
matically cancel a contextual enrichment. Interpretation and construction of
legal texts, and especially of the Constitution, involves motivated reasoning;
vested interested or passionate ideologues may create controversy about impli-
catures that would be recognized by competent speakers motivated by a desire
to understand the text.
With these alterations in mind, we might reformulate Williams’ proposed
principle as follows:
Contextual enrichment should be recognized when competent speakers of
the language at the time the constitutional provision was framed and ratified
would recognize the enrichment of the text given the publicly available con-
text of constitutional communication.
Further questions remain.
49
Contextual enrichment gives rise to special cases
of vagueness and ambiguity. When the content of a contextual enrichment
is vague, the enrichment creates a construction zone. Another possibility is
that competent speakers with knowledge of the publicly available context of
constitutional communication would disagree about what the content of the
enrichment is. This is a special case of ambiguity, “contextual ambiguity.”
Usually, semantic ambiguity can be resolved by reference to context; in the
case of implicative ambiguity, context creates the ambiguity. Of course, it
might be the case that the ambiguity appears when some subset of the pub-
licly available context of constitutional communication is considered but
resolves in light of the full context. But it is at least theoretically possible
that ambiguity is irreducible, and hence that constitutional construction
will be required.
49
For further discussion of these issues, see Goldsworthy, Supra note 29, 27.