(transcript of CBS News Special, broadcast December 3, 1968, quoting Justice Black: “[w]ell,
I’ll read you the part of the First Amendment that caused me to say there are absolutes in our
Bill of Rights . . . Now, if a man were to say this to me out on the street, ‘Congress shall make
no law respecting an establishment of religion’ – that’s the First Amendment – I would think:
68
Lawrence B. Solum
congressional powers, and to the Ninth Amendment (proposed and ratified at
the same time as the First) that forbids constructions of the Constitution that
deny or disparage rights retained by the people on the basis that other rights
(including the freedom of speech) are enumerated. And the First Amendment
was framed and ratified in a particular historical context, some of which was
publicly shared by those who attended the Philadelphia convention, some by
the state ratifying conventions, and some by “We the People,” the citizenry of
the United States. This publicly available context of constitutional communi-
cation may have enriched the meaning of the phrase “freedom of speech” –
giving relatively more clarity and determinacy to a phrase that would be highly
underdeterminate considered out of context. This enriched meaning is the
communicative content of the Free Speech Clause.
Now consider the legal content that is associated with the Free Speech
Clause. Consider the example mentioned above: free speech doctrine is sub-
stantially more complex and rich than the communicative content conveyed
by the text of the First Amendment – even taking contextual enrichment into
account. The legal content of free speech doctrine includes a variety of com-
plex legal rules governing a wide variety of topics ranging from the regulation
of billboards to campaign finance to child pornography on the Internet. Take
billboard regulation as an example: the Supreme Court has articulated what
it calls “the law of billboards”
16
as a subset of free speech doctrine, but it is
clearly the case that the full legal content of this body of rules is not contained
in the communicative content of the Free Speech Clause. Obviously, the law
of billboards is not in the semantic content of the First Amendment; neither
the word billboard nor a synonym appears in the text. Almost as obviously,
the precise content of the law of billboards is not a logical implication of the
semantic content. And when we add the contribution made by the publicly
available context of constitutional utterance, it is also obvious that the law of
billboards was not in the communicative content of the First Amendment:
competent speakers of English who were aware of the publicly available con-
text would not have thereby been able to predict the precise contours of the
Supreme Court’s billboard doctrines.
The point is that context contributes to communicative content. So far, I
have illustrated this point using judicially crafted constitutional doctrine, but
the same phenomenon can occur in the political branches with constitutional
constructions articulated explicitly (e.g., in opinion letters or preambles) or
assumed implicitly, in both individual actions and settled practices.
16
Metromedia Inc. v. City of San Diego, 453 U.S. 490, 501 (1981).