The Platonic Conception of the Israeli Constitution
291
Law and Positive Law. Some positive legal systems may be more just and
therefore closer to Natural Law, and some not, but the two are conceptually
different, and there is no causal or conceptual necessary connection between
them. Therefore their relationship is usually portrayed as one of conflict – the
Natural Law that lead Antigone to bury her brother, in the Greek play that
carries her name, conflicted with Creon’s positive law that forbade it.
66
The
relationship of Form and Substance and of Idea and Matter is, on the other
hand, one of reflection and manifestation. This is the reason why the act of
bridging the gap between the imperfect constitutional text and the perfect
Idea of the constitution is usually referred to by judges and lawyers as an act
of “interpretation” rather than an act of conflict and of “overriding.” The true
Form is thought to lie somehow in the heart of its imperfect manifestation in
the constitutional text, and the judge, interpreting the text, only finds it there
and brings it to light.
Fourth, the Platonic conception can also help explain the extensive use of
foreign constitutional law in the jurisprudence of the Israeli Supreme Court,
67
as well as in the jurisprudence of other constitutional courts that share this
model, such as the German
68
and the Canadian
69
ones. The same attempt at
getting at the ideal Form that is embedded somehow in the imperfect text, is
shared by constitutional judges all over the world, as different constitutions are
all manifestations (flawed and imperfect each in their own way) of this ideal.
Since judges all over share the same project they can be aided by the products
of each other.
Fifth and finally, the Platonic conception can also explain why judges can
annul constitutional provisions even without a “super” constitutional text that
lies above the constitution. Judges can invalidate even the constitution itself, if
it deviates too much from the Platonic Idea of a constitution. This conclusion
may sound extreme, but it is also part of actual Israeli constitutional doctrine.
66
Sophocles, Antigone (trans. Robert Fagles) (Penguin Classics 2015). It has been pointed out to
me that this perception of the relationship between Natural Law and Positive Law is true from
a positivistic perspective, but not necessarily from a Natural Law one. I thank Steve Smith for
this point.
67
See Iddo Porat, “The Use of Foreign Law in Israeli Constitutional Adjudication”, in Gideon
Sapir, Daphne Barak-Erez and Aharon Barak (eds.), Israeli Constitutional Law in the Making
(Hart Publishing 2013), 151.
68
Hannes Unberath, “Comparative Law in the German Courts,” in Guy Canivet, Mads
Andenæs and Duncan Fairgrieve (eds.), Comparative Law before the Courts (British Institute
of International and Comparative Law 2004), 307.
69
Peter McCormick, “The Supreme Court of Canada and American Citations 1945–94: A Sta-
tistical Overview” (1997) 8 Supreme Court Law Review 527; Peter McCormick, “American
Citations and the McLachlin Court: An Empirical Study” (2009) 47 Osgoode Hall Law
Journal 83.
292
Iddo Porat
According to Justice Barak and other Justices, the Supreme Court could inval-
idate a Basic Law if it conflicted in a strong way with the “basic principles of
the system.”
70
This doctrine is associated by these judges with the doctrine
of “unconstitutional constitutional amendments” known also in other consti-
tutional systems,
71
but it seems more far-reaching, as the unconstitutionality
in the Israeli case would not emanate from the constitution itself, but from
higher principles – the Idea of a constitution according to my interpretation.
9.4. The Platonic Conception taken to the Extreme,
Justifications, and Answers to Objections
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |