Separation of Powers: A Theory for the Modern State (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009),
ch 1.
The Evolution of Natural Law in Ireland
455
While the idea that there may be a political or social value in maintaining
invisibility on certain issues shares some similarities with Sunstein’s work on
incompletely theorised agreements, the Irish experience is quite different in
that it reverses his preferred focus on outcomes instead of abstractions. While
Sunstein acknowledges the possibility of ‘incompletely specified agreements’
in the constitutional sphere, his work is more interested in (and advocates
strongly) a judicial approach that consciously avoids discussion of general
principles in favour of low-level principles and particular outcomes.
56
A pre-
sumption against high-level reasoning would, in his view, provide a prudential
and minimalist means of promoting consensus by obtaining no more agree-
ment than is necessary.
The Irish experience, by contrast, suggests that these abstract high-level
principles may have value as a unifying source of social stability. While citi-
zens will disagree on the appropriate outcome in particular cases, there may be
scope for a reciprocal consensus on the system’s commitment to certain broad
normative goals. As the discussion of the Preamble showed, this can be based
in part on the constitution’s declaration of a normative identity which might
be anticipated to be socially or politically attractive. There is also, however,
a more actively long-term sense in which the use of abstract constitutional
norms, the content of which are invisible, may foster stability. This follows
from the participatory and reason-focused nature of constitutional adjudica-
tion. Where citizens differ on particular outcomes, high-level constitutional
norms can offer a grammar of disagreement that encourages deliberation on
these different views. The significance of this is that any disagreement remains
internal to the constitutional order. Furthermore, the disagreement is dealt
with in a way that promotes reciprocity and reason-giving. This affirms both
the autonomy of the individual and legitimacy of the system by providing the
loser with a public justification of the outcome. From the point of view of both
the particular outcome and the general reputation of the system, there is an
obvious incentive for that justification to be expressed in terms that are more
likely to enjoy broad social acceptance. General normative principles provide
one way that this can be achieved.
This offers support for a hypothesis that textual indeterminacy – the pos-
sibility of invisible values – may not necessarily be the problem sometimes
suggested in Ireland; in fact, it may be that this incompleteness creates a space
for pluralistic contestation within a framework that makes disagreement man-
ageable. This has some parallels with Rawls’ concept of public reason without
56
Cass R. Sunstein, ‘Incompletely Theorized Agreements’ (1995) 108 Harvard Law Review 1733,
1739.
456
Eoin Carolan
necessarily imposing the same kind of substantive constraints on permissible
reasons. Rather, the more basic point that – whether for moral,
57
minimialist
58
or Machiavellian
59
considerations – a process that explains its outcomes by
reasons that invite a social consensus has the potential to support constitu-
tional stability. The lesson from Ireland might therefore be that recourse to
invisible normative values is not only an inevitable response to textual ambi-
guity, but also a systemically valuable aspect of constitutional adjudication.
However, the Irish experience also cautions that this invisibility presents an
enduring challenge to the authority and status of the principles involved, so
that they may prove more susceptible to political and social pressures than
other more visible aspects of the constitutional order.
57
John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York, NY: Columbia University Press, 2010). See also
John Rawls, ‘The Domain of the Political and Overlapping Consensus (1989) 64 New York
University Law Review 233.
58
Sunstein, Supra note 56; Cass R. Sunstein, Legal Reasoning and Political Conflict (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1996).
59
Maritn Loughlin, ‘Constitutional Law: The Third Order of the Political’ in Nicholas Bam-
forth and Peter Leyland (eds.), Public Law in a Multi-Layered Constitution (Oxford: Hart
Publishing, 2003).
457
16.1. Introduction
The Italian Constitutional Court was introduced by the Constitution of 1948.
It was a year in which a constitutional democracy was established in Italy as a
form of government in which sovereignty belongs to the people who exercise
it within the limits established by a “rigid” written Constitution (Article 1 of
the Constitution). The rigidity of the Constitution is entrenched by means of
a more complex amendment procedure compared with the ordinary legisla-
tive one (Article 138 of the Constitution).
In addition to its rigidity, the 1948 Italian Constitution was conceived by
its Constituent Fathers as a “supreme” norm, hierarchically superior to the
laws approved by Parliament. The position the Constitution holds within the
sources of law is protected by its more complex amendment procedure, as well
as by the constitutional justice system which, in fact, envisages a Constitutional
Court with the power, inter alia, to declare the illegitimacy of laws and legally
binding acts produced by the State and the Regional organs.
1
Since the start of its activity as privileged interpreter of the Constitution
in 1956, the Court has displayed a high level of interpretative creativity and
activism in its interpretation of the text of the Constitution.
2
This is possi-
ble also thanks to the formulation of constitutional norms conceived by the
Constituent Fathers as provisions capable of adapting to the changing times.
Thus, the Italian Constitution, like many other constitutional texts, has both a
visible and an invisible content, and the Constituent Fathers were well aware
1
For the other competences of the Italian Constitutional Court see Section
16.2
.
2
Tania Groppi, Le grandi decisioni della Corte cosituzionale italiana (Naples: Editoriale Scien-
tifica, 2010) XII.
16
“Additive Judgments”
A Way to Make the Invisible Content of the
Italian Constitution Visible
Irene Spigno
Inter-American Academy of Human Rights.
458
Irene Spigno
of this aspect of constitutional invisibility within the 1948 text. The invisibility
of the Italian Constitution, to be considered as “extra-constitutional under-
standing,” as Rosalind Dixon and Adrienne Stone point out in Chapter 1 in
this book, is mainly linked to two elements. On the one hand, it is a widely
shared opinion that the Republican Constitution was clearly intended to be
a “charter of principles,” since it was originally conceived as regulating the
functioning of the State’s powers. On the other hand, its invisibility derives
from the specific structure of the Constituent Assembly, whose composition
was a mirror of the post-war political panorama.
3
In that period, Italian society
was divided into two main political blocs with hugely differing goals and rela-
tionships with the dominant social forces: on one side, there was the Catholic
party (Democrazia Cristiana) and, on the other side, the left-wing parties
( Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |