2. Distributive justice
Distributive justice regards the rules of how to organise the distribution of material
and immaterial goods to actors (persons, classes, countries) seen as members of a group
of a given dimension (citizens of a country, countries of the world). Plain examples
178 Ethics and politics
of the rules are distribution proportional to the personal merits in meritocracy, to the
hours worked on the workplace, to everybody’s needs and/or skills in an ideal society.
Some of these topics are known to us from our reflections on equality, but now the
corresponding models come provisioned explicitly with the predicate ‘just’.
From Plato onwards philosophers have theorised several models of polity based
on increasingly elaborate conceptions of justice. The most sophisticated and, at the
same time, the most interested in a political model of justice, ‘the first virtue of social
institutions’ (Rawls 1999a, 3), remains John Rawls’s theory of justice as developed
in 1971 (now Rawls 1999a, 1993 and 1999b). The purpose of Rawls’s research is
how to ideally set up a polity or ‘well-ordered society’ whose institutions are based
on justice as fairness; he understands this model of a constitutional democracy to be
an alternative to utilitarianism, which is, in his view, unfit to secure the basis of such
a regime because it gives the ‘calculus of social interests’ (Rawls 1999a, 4) priority
over the liberties of equal citizenship. While rerunning the basics of the contractar-
ian tradition, from Locke to Rousseau and most importantly to Kant, Rawls designs
an ‘original position’ in which citizens find out what the best principles of a just
society are expected to look like. In doing so, their impartiality is assured by a ‘veil
of ignorance’ that prevents them from knowing their social status, their possession
of natural assets and abilities, the conception of the good they may adhere to, the
generation of which they are a part (Rawls 1999a, 118–123). They are thus enabled
to determine the best principles of society removed from particular interests and
ideologies they would otherwise tend to let prevail. The outcome consists of the
principle of greatest equal liberty for all and of a second principle, called the differ-
ence principle; they are both developments of a more general conception of justice:
All social values – liberty and opportunity, income and wealth, and the social
bases of self respect – are to be distributed equally unless an unequal distribu-
tion of any, or all, of these values is to everybody’s advantage.
(Rawls 1999a, 54)
The difference principle is contained in the qualification ‘unless . . .’ and is fur-
ther specified in §46 of A Theory of Justice in the sense that social and economic
inequalities are to be arranged so that they ‘are to the greatest benefit of the least
advantaged’ (Rawls 1999a, 266). This can, for example, justify fiscal policies that
redistribute income in favour of the less advantaged layers of society, but also a
rejection of radical egalitarianism, which would cancel the stimuli given to the
efficiency of national economy by individual aspirations to higher income, to be
attained by business creation and higher productivity. In Rawls’s order of priority,
efficiency ranks, in any case, after equal liberty and welfare. The priority given to
a ‘system of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar system of liberty for all’
(from the First principle as formulated in §46) explains why Rawls’s conception has
been seen as the peak of (left-leaning) liberalism in the American sense of the word.
In Political Liberalism (1993) Rawls corrected his own previous view of justice based
on liberalism as a ‘comprehensive doctrine’ (including a theory of moral values and
metaphysics) and focused on the political character of democratic liberalism. This
Justice and solidarity 179
stance is deemed to facilitate reaching an ‘overlapping consensus’ (another key item
in Rawls’s vocabulary) among different conceptions of justice, provided the debate
is regulated by ‘public reason’, which acknowledges only rules that can be justified
in front of those to whom the rules apply; for example, civic rules deriving from
a particular religion are not of this sort, since among the citizens to whom they
are expected to apply some or many are no believers and are not ready to accept
religious justifications of those rules.
Of the innumerable debates ignited by Rawls’s philosophy since 1971 I shall name
only a few here: first the dissent about international justice that unfolded within his
own followers; then, in the last part of the section, follows a brief account of the cri-
tique launched by what we could dub the opposition (Nozick’s libertarianism, com-
munitarianism, Derrida). Only later on we will deal with the existential question as to
how far general normative theory or ‘ideal theory’ makes sense in political philosophy.
Rawls conceives of international society as a society of peoples ( scil. countries),
not free and equal individuals; remaining far away of any cosmopolitan egalitarian-
ism, he sees for wealthier countries only a duty of ‘assistance’ to ‘burdened’ societies,
helping them attain decent and stable domestic institutions that respect human
rights; this does not include a duty to narrow the gap between rich and poor. This
is, with various arguments, criticised by cosmopolitan theorists of justice such as
Charles Beitz (2000) and Thomas Pogge (2001), and this discussion has given birth
to a current of studies and suggestions called ‘global justice’ that issues and assesses
policy proposals concerning problems such as poverty, the reduction of illiteracy,
the promotion of gender equality, a better food production and distribution, but
also issues of international criminal justice, particularly after the creation of the
International Criminal Court. Contrary to this tendency, David Miller (2000) has
argued that, as nation states are ethical communities, we owe to our fellow-nationals
duties that are not only different from, but also more extensive than, the duties we
owe to human beings as such.
My thoughts in Chapter 7 on how to treat with respect and fairness the people of
the far future may seem to come closer to this current, except that they differ from
‘global justice’ for two reasons: first, my proposal results from a political philosophy of
man-made lethal challenges, not from elaborating on general normative principles.
Second, the time universalism I propose finds correspondence neither in Rawls’s
principle of the ‘just savings’ for future generations nor in the global justice literature,
focused as it is almost exclusively on space universalism. A further difference lies in
the political (as different from moral) reflection that reducing inequality and promot-
ing retributive justice for human rights violations worldwide is not only a normative
issue of justice, but also an issue of stability and peace. Egalitarian steps, for example,
allowing more and more immigration from less wealthy countries because all human
beings have a right to what Rawls dubs primary goods, cannot be undertaken simply
out of their rightness, but must find the consent of the hosting populations, which
cannot be expected to flow from discourses of charity or justice, but as the result of
a well-designed political process, in which the interests of both guests and hosts are
both taken into consideration. Large-scale and efficient development aid delivered in
the emigration countries (side-stepping if necessary their rogue regimes) can prevent
180 Ethics and politics
mass emigration, which is unavoidably tied to human suffering. In any case, the cat-
egory of solidarity fits these problems better than that of justice, as we shall see.
* * *
Opposition to Rawls’s theory of justice came up vigorously three years after its
publication with Nozick’s minarchism or theory of the minimal state (Nozick 1974),
in which freedom, rather than distributive justice, is the leading principle and ‘end-
state theories’, so-called because the final distribution is normatively fixed once
and for all, are rejected. Nozick favours a historical theory of distribution, which
respects property as it was originally distributed or later acquired, though a rec-
tification procedure for past injustices is also foreseen. In his utopia people who
disagree with the state of affairs in their own society can leave and found another
one. In this extreme case of ideal theory (see below), the relationship between lib-
erty and equality is brought back to the radical opposition that marked the original
tension between liberalism and democracy.
A more systemic and less otherworldly opposition to the theory of justice and
liberalism altogether is represented by communitarianism, a wide field including phi-
losophers of quite diverse orientation such as: Alisdair MacIntyre (1981), Michael
Sandel (1982),
3
Charles Taylor (1989), Michael Walzer (1983). The landscape here is
totally different: not the isolated, atomized, unencumbered individuals of liberalism,
who in this communitarian description are all driven by self-interest, but the com-
munity with its traditions and customs. In it alone can individuals achieve a sense
of their associate existence in a mindset that is guided by the search for meaningful
ends rather than the enacting of abstract rights. The good is more important and
a better motivating force than the right, as the communitarians believe in a shift
backwards from a deontological to a teleological posture.
4
In the communitarian rejection of liberal individualism themes come up which
were all anticipated in Hegel’s critique of Kant’s moral philosophy; this was sort of
inevitable, since Rawls himself presents his theory as a rerunning of Kant under-
taken after (and against) the utilitarian wave that went through (Anglo-American)
thought in the last two centuries. Kant reborn could not but evoke a renewed
Hegelian wave, though communitarians lack Hegel’s view on world history. They
do rather echo the anti-liberal and anti-capitalist, in a word anti-modern, stance
of Romanticism and recall to mind the conception of community/ Gemeinschaft
examined in Chapter 4. Though not without influence on the philosophical debate
in Europe, communitarianism has been almost exclusively an American phenom-
enon, and the ‘community’ it intends can only be fully understood by keeping in
mind American social history and the particular aura this word is surrounded with
in American political and religious language.
A critical comment on the liberal notion of justice has been formulated in
France by Jacques Derrida (1930–2004), the philosopher of the now popular
deconstructionism. He has pointed out the amount of force and willful decision
that lies at the origin of whatever system of justice, which must therefore remain
Justice and solidarity 181
self-contradictory and impossible; his philosophy of democracy is, rather, centred
on the notion of hospitality, along with the tension between the unconditional and
the conditional versions of it.
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |