What
drives people to politics 203
The identity of a democratic community with its openness and integrative
force belongs primarily here. Yet it is also true that a democratic identity can-
not remain an intellectual argument, if it is to drive people, and is best embed-
ded in positive emotions of solidarity and equal respect.
• remembering Chapter 3, a fourth driving element must be acknowledged:
institutional (in the sense of institution-driven)
action. Individuals, as well as
groups, (administrative or political bodies, parties and more) do not every sin-
gle day reinvent their course of action driven by strategy, passion or ideal: in
normal times, a major component of their actions is the conformity to (or the
endeavour to reinterpret or change) the grid of rules that allow for the exist-
ence and continuity of the polity, which is also the
venue in which to enact
the life plans of individuals and groups. Only in the now seldom revolutionary
times this type of action loses terrain, but does not disappear, waiting for new
institutions to start working. Institution-driven behaviour should not be mis-
taken for proneness to apply rules whatever their justification or however based
one’s own assessment; it only implies the acknowledgement that at the end of
the day interests, ideals and identities must find expression in rules embodied
in institutions, both informal and formal. The predominance of the latter bears
witness to the crucial, though not exclusive role of the law – already seen in
Chapter 4, §5 and again in Chapter 10 with regard to Habermas – in shaping
and upholding the old and new arrangements in which we manage the busi-
ness of life.
A major examination
of the four-tiered grid, and in particular, of all the inter-
twinements between the four elements would require more space than is given in
an Epilogue. The grid is little more than a stub, in the hope it is useful to put some
order to hints found all across the book. It also has the task to stress the distinc-
tive nature of the four driving moments, which become very much intermingled
within the concrete actors’ behaviour, but must be mentally kept from each other.
Any attempt to explain an event or process on the basis of just one of these driv-
ers must fail, given the mix of high and low, reasonable
and murky of which our
behaviour as individuals and groups consist. Against all reductionism, for example,
it would be wrong to subsume acting on universalistic, principle-driven moti-
vations under strategic, self-centred behaviour, as the less refined realist writers,
modern followers of the Sophist Trasimachos remembered in Chapter 9, §1, do
with the pretension to unmask the hoax – as they say – perpetrated by idealistic
actors who claim to act for the sake of humanity or the law while pursuing their
own interest. This attitude does not have more truth than the conventional wis-
dom heeded by the people for whom ‘all politics is a dirty business’. The truth
regarding such a multilayered being as a human and such a contradictory business
as politics is more articulated than what can be unveiled by simplifications and
alleged ‘cynical lucidity’.
Twin cases of reductionism can also be found with regard to passions. The older
one wants passions to be altogether a factor
of corruption for politics, leading to
204 Epilogue
irrational and destructive results, and calls for having them chastised by reason.
We have already argued that even the best political life does not develop without
an emotional component, while passions do not build a compact bunch and a
differentiation must be drawn between them. The younger step into reduction-
ism goes in the opposite direction: politics was always icy and dull, far from the
hearts of the people, women in particular, and should finally be put in the flow of
positive, community-building emotions. This proposal forgets about the obstacle
represented by the fact that, left alone, without the company of reason (both as
calculus and moral reason), emotions cannot be easily discerned into positive or
negative
and can wreak havoc; while, along with motivation and purpose, politics
also includes policy making and controlling public administration, all tasks in which
emotions can replace reasoning and bargaining as little as, say, the much praised
‘gift economy’ can replace the market and the money in advanced societies – the
problem being rather how far the two economies can coexist.
* * *
This book ends with a warning that is at the same time an invitation.
Politics as represented here is politics looked at through the lenses of concepts, an
irreplaceable instrument – a political philosopher tends to believe – to understand it
and also to find a firmer ground to orient oneself in political action. Yet it’s a long
way from the concept to the understanding, let alone the handling of any concrete
political situation in which we can get involved as participants or observers. On this
long path it is not political philosophy that can provide food for thought, though
expansion and refinement of the concepts explained here would help. Armed with
the tools offered in this book, the reader is rather invited to plunge into a wealth
of documents that are closer to the flesh and blood of real politics: history books
primarily, about
general history as well as, say, social or military history. Then come
biographies and autobiographies: the well-written ones give a vivid picture of
how policy making and consensus seeking, the two main components of concrete
politics, come about or end in failure and omission. They also give the reader the
advantage of getting the sense of a dimension that has not been discussed in this
book because it is highly elusive and almost impossible to conceptualize: the role
of
personality in politics, once a popular theme among ancient writers of politics,
first of all Plutarch.
Another invitation is to read sociological (first of all from economic sociology)
and anthropological literature that can give a fresh and well-documented image of
how things are evolving in society and politics, thus helping readapt or discard con-
cepts that have lost currency in a changing reality. A further fascinating source, dull
that their language may sound, are sentences issued by high courts – national such
as the US Supreme Court or the German
Bundesverfassungsgericht as
well as inter-
national such as the European Court of Human Rights – in cases of political and
ethical relevance. This kind of attention must now extend to the books based on
hard science concerned with the events in nature (or rather in the human handling