198 Ethics and politics
5 The republican tradition has been in the past half century investigated by historians such
as J. G. A. Pocock (1975) and Quentin Skinner (1978).
6 A major example of this literature remains Arendt’s essay
Lying in Politics in Arendt 1972,
1–47. Politics that is indifferent to the (argumentatively verifiable) truth, hence often
hostile to it, seems to represent a very new chapter, which
The Economist of 10 Septem-
ber 2016 has dubbed ‘post-truth politics’. Also, a philosophical inquiry into this complex
under the conditions of the digital age would be welcome.
7 Weber’s main text in this respect is
Politik als Beruf/
Politics as a Vocation a talk given in
Munich at the end of 1919, a few months before Weber died, at the age of fifty-six, of
the Spanish flu pandemic that ravaged the world immediately after the Great War; it has
been already quoted several times in this volume (Weber 1919a).
8 The original move in this direction was made by Lyotard (1979).
9 A superb example of both these moves was Dr. Martin Luther King’s ability to force or
persuade President Lyndon B. Johnson to use his own clout as President and his shrewd-
ness as former Democratic majority leader in the Senate in order to forward the passage
of the Civil Rights Act and the Voting Rights Act in the US Congress back in 1964–65,
cf. Kotz 2005.
10 For reformist realism see Scheuerman 2011.
11 Eleanor Roosevelt (1884–1962), who as First Lady of the United States had acted against
racial and gender discrimination, was the driving force behind the drafting of UDHR,
see https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/File:EleanorRooseveltHumanRights.png.
12 I have examined these aspects of ‘normative political philosophy’ in the case of climate
ethics (see Cerutti 2016).
13 The key figure, in this sense, was US President Woodrow Wilson (1856–1924, in office
from 1913 through 1921), whose interventionist ‘democratic idealism’ as a tenet of for-
eign policy continues to build one of the recurrent strains in US diplomatic history.
14 The term ‘decent’ describes ‘nonliberal societies whose basic institutions meet certain
specified conditions of political right and justice’ (Rawls 1999b, 3n2).
15 This label also had the advantage of not making explicit any reference to Marxism, suspi-
cious to public authorities both in Germany and the USA in the Thirties.
16 Walther Benjamin, a close friend Adorno’s, was never a member of the Institute, even
if he was supported by them; nor can his thought be labelled as belonging to Critical
Theory.
17 See above Chapter 3, §2, note 3, Neumann also wrote
Behemoth, an early political con-
ceptualization of the National Socialist regime (1942).
18 ‘German
Lebenswelt, . . . the world as immediately or directly experienced in the sub-
jectivity of everyday life, as sharply distinguished from the objective “worlds” of the sci-
ences, which employ the methods of the mathematical sciences of nature’ (from https://
www.britannica.com/topic/life-world). The term was introduced in philosophy by
Edmund Husserl (1859–1938) and developed in the phenomenological sociology of
Alfred Schütz (1899–1959).
19 In Marx’s vocabulary, this means giving a higher relevance to
Überbau/superstructure in
comparison to the economic basis of society and politics; for this terminology see Marx
1859.
20 The now popular concept of postmaterialism was introduced by the American sociolo-
gist Ronald Inglehart (Inglehart 1977).
21 As Marx wrote to F.A. Sorge (Marx 1877).
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: