138
praiseworthy for their lack of acting grossly immorally. This would certainly
change the way we think about morality with respect to grossly immoral acts.
There remains a question about the value of knowing whether refraining from a
grossly immoral
action was praiseworthy or not, vis-à-vis considering the moral
weight of the averted harms of immoral acts. Moreover, the worry about being able
to ascribe moral blame and moral praise in the God Machine scenario seems to be
putting the cart before the horse. If we see the accuracy of our ascription of moral
blame and moral praise as having a solely instrumental value in promoting (via
rewarding with praise) or discouraging (via expressing blame) certain acts, by
praising everyone indiscriminately, we can assure that the deserving are rewarded.
Inaccurate moral praise for those who indeed formed the intention would only
encourage the kind of thinking and predisposition that lead to forming a bad intent,
yet we may rest assured that this would not result in grossly immoral acts anyway,
since the God Machine would intervene if such intention was formed again.
There are two crucial ways in which the God Machine scenario differs from
Frankfurt’s thought experiment. Firstly, in Frankfurt’s scenario, Jones’ actions are
attributable to Jones since Black did not exert his influence on Jones. If Black was
going to act is such a way to make Jones refrain from acting immorally, and he had
to exert force to cause Jones to refrain from such action, Jones would not be
considered to be praiseworthy for refraining. The God
Machine scenario is more
ambiguous because there is no obvious external coercion as would be the case if
Black threatened Jones with a gun, or employed persuasion which would still leave
Jones’ being able to consider the influence - instead the God Machine acts directly
on intentions without the knowledge of the influenced actor and thus, in Harris’
words ‘bypasses morality’. The influence itself cannot be modified or responded to
by the agent, at least not in a conscious way. I examine the implications of that in
later parts of this chapter. At this moment let us focus on the second way in which
the God Machine scenario differs from Jones & Black thought experiment – the
issue of the problems created by the fact that the intervention happens without
agents’ knowledge.
139
The God Machine scenario could undermine the value of moral praise. The first
way this could happen relates to the undermining of reliable self-knowledge coming
with the God Machine scenario. Since in Savulescu and Persson’s (2012a) world,
the person forming such an intention would not know that this intention has been
changed by an
authority outside of herself, all those subject to the God Machine
interventions – both those who would have ‘changed their mind’ and those who
would not – would have good reasons to doubt whether they deserve praise.
Another way in which the value of moral praise could be undermined would be
analogical to a situation when students are indiscriminately praised for their effort
and hard work, even though some of the students did not study at all while others
did. It matters to us that the praise is deserved and given on the basis of a roughly
accurate assessment of reality. Thus, even though there were some instrumental
reasons for continuing to praise, ultimately the undermining of the value of such
praise could plausibly lead the God Machine society
to abandon any talk about
praise and blame, at least in so far as that includes taking credit for living in a
society without grossly immoral acts. Those whose moral actions were
praiseworthy could perhaps still freely choose to do the right thing, yet, when the
stakes are high, their actions would cease to be a subject of moral praise.
23
However, perhaps the above worry is overblown, given that a) we normally do not
expect nor give praise for refraining from grossly immoral actions, b) we presently
are also not certain about the extent to which the apparent moral behaviours (or lack
of grossly immoral acts) of
others are due to their virtue, and c) perhaps the God
Machine could be treated as an instance of moral luck. Let us consider these
reservations in turn.
It could be argued that the undermining of praise for refraining from grossly
immoral actions in the God Machine society is unimportant because we normally
do not give praise for not doing great evils anyway. Our unwillingness to kill an
innocent person is something we expect and may see as a morally good thing, but
not something deserving of moral praise. It then becomes irrelevant (for our doubts
about moral praise in the God Machine scenario) whether the inability to kill an
23
Although so far this section has simplified the issue of praise
and blame in relation to
action, this way of elucidating the implications of the scenario shed light on why we could
find the God Machine scenario not only alien but also troubling.
140
innocent person is due to insurmountable squeamishness, strongly held values or
preferences, or the God Machine– as we would not give any praise anyway. The
question of moral praise and blame in relation to a person’s preferences seems to
become more important when we consider an intention to act rather than refrain
from acting. The question of moral praise and blame in relation to a person’s
preferences seems to become important when we consider those actions one intends
to commit rather than those actions one refrains from committing.
However, this seems not to be the case when a temptation (a
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: