5.3.4. The ‘full human life involves suffering’ argument
Regardless of the direct epistemic value of letting us know where we stand,
unpleasant experiences can also be regarded as a necessary and valuable part of a
full human life. As problems are medicalized, a critic might say, they are construed
as pathological and in need of fixing, while some kinds of suffering should not be
fixed.
In his critique of the process of medicalization, Illich (1975) argued that
medicalization is associated with iatrogenesis, in which the problems created by
medicine are worse than the solutions it offers to the original condition. Cultural or
structural iatrogenesis may happen when the medical view of, for example, pain,
birth and death changes the meaning that those experiences have to people.
According to Illich (1975) the meaning and the experience of suffering goes beyond
the mere occurrence of physiological pain, and the attitude and meaning we give it
makes a difference to how we live our lives. He further argues that medicalization
leads people to forget about accepting suffering as an inevitable part of their
conscious coping with reality, and instead learn to interpret every ache as an
indicator of the need for ‘padding or pampering.’ Meanwhile, the signs and
experience of suffering were traditionally seen as signals with a function of eliciting
a response from an agent. Thus, Illich sees medicalization as the process of
detaching pain from its cultural context (and thus meaning) and aiming to annihilate
it.
It is easy to agree with Illich
(1975)
that the easier it is to make the pain just go
away, the more temptation there is to alleviate the pain and ignore its cause, thus
potentially bypassing the motivational and epistemic value of pain. On the other
hand, there are many instances of unnecessary pain (in the sense of not serving any
epistemic or motivational functions, or where the benefit brought by those functions
is outweighed by harms) and alleviation of it would be appropriate. For example, it
seems unnecessary to be dying in pain if one can die calmly and without pain; after
85
the function the a pain of a broken leg has been fulfilled, it seems unnecessary to
continue to be in a strong pain. Illich’s argument holds only to the extent that we
forget about the epistemic and motivational functions of pain.
An account inspired by existentialists may see anxiety as valuable because the
experience of anxiety disrupts immersion in the usual projects and identity-creating
roles, and is a part of the experience of oneself as a moral agent, responsible for
one’s decisions (Moran, 2000). Klerman
(1972) made a more general point that
Western culture developed under the influence of Ancient Greek and Christian
traditions, which have assigned value to the suffering that comes with human
problems. In a similar vein, Parens (2011) cites Shenk’s (2005) account of how
Abraham Lincoln’s ‘melancholia’ was not just a huge burden, but also a crucial
ingredient in his great life, this being but one recent example of that view. Thus,
one may say that suffering may be seen as valuable and necessary for a full human
existence and pharmacological interference with it as impairing our ability to
flourish as people.
The critics of this approach sometimes call it ‘pharmacological Calvinism.’ The
phrase was first used in the 1970s by Klerman, who thought that ‘[i]mplicit in the
theory of therapeutic change is the philosophy of personal growth, basically a
secular view of salvation through good works’. He describes ‘pharmacological
Calvinists’ underlying intuition to be that
‘if a drug makes you feel good, it not only represents a
secondary form of salvation but somehow it is morally wrong
and the user is likely to suffer retribution with either
dependence, liver damage … or some other form of medical-
theological damnation.’ (1972, p. 3)
Parens notes that ‘[i]nsofar as those traditions celebrated suffering for which there
were no medical remedies, Klerman must be right that at least to some extent those
traditions made a virtue of necessity’ (p. 5). Parens reformulates Klerman’s
thought:
86
‘If pharmacological and psychotherapeutic means can both
achieve the same end – improving how one experiences
herself and the world – then it is irrational and perhaps
inhumane to prefer the more strenuous and expensive
means. It’s irrational not to take a shortcut when
improving human well-being is the destination. We should
be slower to imagine that suffering leads to growth and
understanding, and quicker to remember that sometimes it
just crushes human souls.’ (Parens, 2011, p. 5)
One interpretation of Klerman’s may point to the value of a process (whether or not
it involves suffering) rather than the outcome and the value we might ascribe to
effort and struggle. Parens suggests that Kleman’s view ignores the moments in
which we would think that suffering is a crucial element in a good human life and
gives an example of grieving after a loss of a loved one. He suggests that such
suffering should be endured rather than erased. This points to the fact that not all
ways of improving wellbeing are good in the same way, and we may have reasons
not to choose a ‘shortcut’ to wellbeing.
Although Parens’s example is an intuitively appealing counterexample to
Klerman’s view, we should not let the intuitive appeal get the better of us. The
appeal of the example stems from several sources, and I would propose that we
question the intuitions to which Parens is appealing. The problem, I think, is not
with the medical means of change but rather stems from the fact that we value a
certain engagement with the world in which our feelings both express and reflect
our situation and what we find valuable. The loss of a person we loved rightly
evokes grief which we would be justified in not wanting to immediately remedy.
However, the argument would equally apply if we decided to put ourselves though
a two week course in psychotherapy, one that would alleviate our grief via
attenuating the emotions, so that they would correspond to the emotions felt when
losing a favourite umbrella. Parens would be justified in raising exactly the same
objection and we may justifiably question whether immediate attenuation of grief
amounts to ‘improving how one experiences herself and the world.’ (Parens, 2011,
87
p. 5) However, the problem has little to do with the exact means of medicalization,
nor with medical solutions specifically.
Yet, there is another way in which Klerman's thought can be understood: he can be
seen as criticising the view which focuses on the value of the effort, instead of the
desired outcome. Several commentators emphasised the value of effort in the
pursuit of excellence, and highlighted that medicalizing the problem means looking
for a technological fix – which, even if pragmatically possible, would not be
morally desirable (for discussion see: Cole-Turner, 1998; President’s Council on
Bioethics, 2003, p. 289; Fox, 2005; Olsen, 2006; Schermer, 2008; Goodman, 2010).
Since the scope for improvement and effort will remain, even if we find
technological fixes for many problems and shortcuts to wellbeing, the objection is
weak if it is trying to establish that biomedical enhancements are morally
impermissible or inherently morally suspect because they take away the chance of
morally valuable effort.
On the other hand, it correctly highlights the fact that we may not always have a
reason to take shortcuts, since what we may value about something is the activity or
the process. When solving brain-teasers we might prefer to ‘figure it out’ on our
own, because we value the activity and process over finding an answer that we
could easily find online. Similarly, there is a reason why we may prefer a bike tour
over a flight, even if the end destination is the same. We might also endorse the
suffering of grief, and find a certain degree of existential doubt and anxiety as
reflecting the human condition. However, it appears that it is not ‘the effort’ or
some other similar disconnected property undermined by biomedicine that we
value, but rather the pleasure of the process, the importance of the journey, the
character-shaping or skill-developing consequences of the effort. Similarly,
experiencing pain may be valuable when it stimulates us to come to grips with our
situation, or for its role in expressing and reflecting what we find important. The
extent to which ‘effort’ or pain are necessary to achieve the things we find valuable,
however, is contingent on circumstances and not valuable for its own sake.
Experiencing poverty, hunger, illness or loneliness may open to us an
understanding of others who are in a similarly dire position, an understanding that
88
we would not otherwise have. It might also allow us to appreciate what we have got
to a greater extent, and help us to learn ways of dealing with ourselves and the
world that we otherwise would not learn. It might also stimulate social action. Yet,
the importance of apparently undesirable states and experiences for a full and
flourishing life should be scrutinised; since those experiences are considered to be
necessary for fully experiencing life, they might be subject to the
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |