5.4.
Ethical appraisal: the benefits of medicalization
Parens (2011) argues that discussions of medicalization often rely upon a tacit
distinction between medicalization (which is good) and over-medicalization (which
is bad). He suggests that the cases of PTSD and Alzheimer’s disease, which were
once seen as non-medical problems but are now understood within a medical
context, are examples of ‘good medicalization.’ Similarly, Carter and Hall (2012,
p.231; also Burke, 2011) point out that some scholars use medicalization in a more
positive sense to describe the increased use of effective medical treatments by those
who were previously denied access, either for social reasons or because such
treatments were not available.
What are the potential benefits in the process of medicalization? The critical
appraisal of arguments against medicalization already yielded some indication of
such benefits. Medicalization may allow patients to forge collective identities
around shared experiences, facilitating advocacy efforts and improving recognition
(Browne et al. 2004). It may also shift social perceptions away from a moralistic,
punitive approach to deviance, thereby creating space for increased support and
tolerance (Burke, 2011). On an individual level, medicalization may also legitimize
an individual’s struggles and lead to increased access to services and resources
(Conrad and Potter, 2000; Conrad, 2007). Further, a medical diagnosis may afford
access to social capital associated with ‘the sick role’ (Parsons, 1951).
To provide further counterweight to the critics’ claims I will use the example of
medicalization of addiction to briefly outline some of the benefits that the process
of medicalization may bring. Firstly, and rather obviously, taking a medical
103
perspective may lead to good outcomes following the development of a better
solution to a pre-existing problem. I will not elaborate on this point in great detail,
but medicalization may be desirable because all the potential and actual problems
of medicalization may have less weight than the sometimes devastating results of
addiction.
Secondly, the construction of a problem as at least in part medical rather than
entirely moral may pave the way to easier change, be it via medical or other means.
For example, drug addiction can be regarded as a ‘chronic, relapsing brain disease’
(Leshner, 1997; see also Volcow and Li, 2005) or a matter of personal
responsibility. The former view has been echoed in the attitude of US National
Institutes (NIDA and NIAAA) while the latter is held by many drug users and
families (Bell et al. 2012). That addiction has become medicalized is evident in the
widespread position that addiction is a ‘chronic, relapsing brain disease’ (Leshner,
1997), a claim informed by evidence of neurophysiological and neurochemical
changes present in addiction (Volkow and Li, 2004). As the evidence of
neurological changes that predispose drug users to subsequent use accumulates, the
medical model has become prevalent, replacing the dominant perspective of the 20
th
century that individuals who use drugs were ‘autonomous, self-governing
individuals who wilfully, knowingly, and voluntarily engaged in criminal and
immoral behaviour’ (Carter and Hall, 2008, p. 81).
According to its proponents, the brain disease model of addiction leads to changes
in social and public health policies, which will have the double benefit of providing
more humane and ethical responses to addiction, as well as more effective solutions
to addiction and related harms (Leshner, 1997; McLellan, et al., 2000; Volkow and
Li, 2004; Dackis and O’Brien, 2005). Indeed, the rise of the medical model of
addiction has already played a role in finding novel and beneficial approaches. A
neurophysiological deficit-focus view of addiction led to the development of opioid
substitution therapies, which have shown to be effective in reducing drug use. In
fact, Bell et al. (2012) argue that the primary barrier to increasing the effectiveness
of opioid substitution therapy is residual vestiges of a non-medical, moralizing
approach to drug use evinced by healthcare practitioners working in inpatient
treatment facilities. Furthermore, opioid substitution therapy has its analogue in
approaches to tobacco smoking cessation such as nicotine replacement therapy,
104
which similarly depends on a medicalized, biological dependency perspective on
cigarette smoking (Gartner and Partridge, 2012). Thus, the medical approach comes
with an epistemic stance that facilitates the creation of certain kinds of solutions
that have been shown to increase the chances of kicking the addiction or alleviating
its harmful consequences.
Even where those approaches overemphasise the impact of physiological changes,
such as changes in the reward circuitry in the brain, and unjustifiably
underemphasise the impact of social factors or the strength of habit, the approach
has generated previously unheard of solutions to addiction. Indeed, as the
limitations of the ‘brain disease model’ start to come to the fore, the social,
motivational and habitual influences on maintaining addiction enjoy greater
attention and lead to an integration of pharmacological approaches with other
remedies, such as counselling (National Institute on Drug Abuse, 2012).
Moreover, abandoning the view of addiction as a matter of moral strength or
weakness may decrease blame and facilitate the search for solutions. Firstly, it is
sometimes argued that addiction neuroscience encourages individuals to seek
treatment or empowers them to make choices not to use drugs (Condit et al., 2006;
Carter and Hall, 2012). Secondly, the existence of an authoritative scientific
explanation of addicted individuals’ experiences might increase their willingness to
engage in medical treatment (Hall et al., 2008). There is some empirical support for
this view. Gartner and Partridge (2012) point out that ‘smokers who attribute a
failure to quit to unchangeable intrinsic factors such as personal characteristics have
lower personal quitting intentions and lower quitting self-efficacy’ (p.79).
Similarly, many patients who received a mental health diagnosis describe the sense
of relief coming with decreased self-blame associated with the attribution of
responsibility shift, as well as with a hope for a solution. Paradoxically, although
medicalization is often criticised as labelling and stigmatizing struggling
individuals, it may also lead to de-stigmatisation. Thus, the change in attribution of
responsibility coming with a medical model has the potential to be either
pragmatically harmful or beneficial, depending on whether it increases or decreases
effective coping.
105
Additionally, models of dependency associated with medicalization give rise to a
host of other approaches that recognize the biological basis of addiction. Those
approaches tend not to focus upon abstinence, but upon reducing the risk of harms
unnecessarily associated with drug use. These approaches include needle-exchange
programs and medically-supervised injection sites, both of which are shown to
reduce infections common amongst injection drug users forced to share needles or
inject hurriedly to avoid detection. Those solutions, however, commonly face
protests rooted in a view that the government should not allow drug users to act
illegally and immorally – a perspective commonly associated with Brickman et al.’s
(1982) moral model of addiction. Here, the medical model may facilitate adopting
social policies that prevent a great amount of unnecessary harm.
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |