142
of success in the second case is that the intended victim unexpectedly tripped and
fell to the floor just as the bullet arrived at head-height, by which time the person
with the intention to murder was incapacitated by guards. Since whether the victim
tripped or not and whether the guards arrived quickly enough or not is not
something in control
of either would-be murderer, the case appears to violate the
Control Principle and its corollary.
As Nagel (1979) puts it, ‘Where a significant aspect of what someone does depends
on factors beyond his control, yet we continue to treat
him in that respect as an
object of moral judgment, it can be called moral luck’ (p. 59). Moral luck includes
instances of resultant luck (how things turn out), circumstantial luck (e.g. people
working in Germany in the 1930s vs. those living in another time or place) and
constitutive luck (the luck regarding acquisition of traits and dispositions). As
Feinberg (1970, pp. 34–38) argued, moral luck can affect even our ‘willings’ and
other internal states. According to Nagel’s development of this point, there are
other types of luck that affect not only our actions but also every intention we form
and every exertion of our will. Furthermore, once
these kinds of luck are
recognized, we will see that not one of the factors on which agents' actions depend
is immune to luck. Those who formed the intention to commit gross immorality and
were prevented from acting on it by the God Machine, at least for the purposes of
moral praise and blame, could be seen as being like those whose victims tripped or
those who, through a chain of lucky coincidences, changed their minds.
Consider the example of Wilson Jr. who formed an intention to kill in revenge, yet
on the way to commit the murder passed through a student protest and was
mistakenly arrested on suspicion of another offence.
With his phone call from
prison, he intended to get his friend to put forward bail so he could carry out his
plan. However, influenced by the soothing conversation with the friend and the
passage of time, his intention changed by the time he was released. Were it not for
the
accidental arrest, he would have killed. The God Machine could be seen as a
rather ‘hands-on’ instance of (inescapable) moral luck.
One could object that there is something relevantly different for the ascription of
praise and blame between the God Machine scenario
and the instances of moral
luck discussed above: in the God Machine scenario the agent is neither responsive
143
to reasons nor subject to a lucky coincidence or favourable circumstances, but
rather directly affected. Let us imagine that a segment of the God Machine society
raised this objection and as a result, the God Machine was improved.
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: