42 What is politics?
in
historia magistra vitae died some two centuries ago,
11
and so did three or four dec-
ades age the notion that a philosophy of history (Hegelianism, Marxism, progres-
sivism) can show the meaning of it and tell us where to head for. No such belief
can exempt us from making ourselves our own normative choices in the middle
of something like Weber’s ‘politheism of values’ mentioned in Chapter 1. Yet along
with political science, history remains an essential dimension in which the political
philosopher can reconnect to the variety and diversity of human life in social and
political communities. The constitutional abstractness of philosophical thinking can
only be strengthened by the challenge of conceptualizing ever new processes and
events, rather than being exclusively busy with a sort of secluded self-refinement. In
Chapter 7 on global challenges I shall try to show what this means.
The other version of history that matters for political philosophy is the
history
of political philosophy (or thought). By introducing this field, I am way far from
implying the historicist sense that today’s political philosophy cannot be but the
result and development of what our predecessors have thought about politics. It
is now clear that this author is rather inclined to believe that political philoso-
phy consists of conceptualizing new aspects and problems of the reality we live
in, being aware of what history contributes to their explanation and also with
a view towards the future – as far as this outlook can be prudently performed.
Taking stock of the conceptual languages philosophers of the past have invented
and refined remains, however, an indispensable passage if we want to start our
reflection on the present at the highest possible level of skilled formulation and
elaboration – or simply avoid blunders or refished arguments introduced as if
they were fresh discoveries. We hardly expect nowadays to meet ‘eternal truths’
in philosophy, but with respect to the mental structures
that seem to be rooted in
our anthropology – language, power, fear, freedom, sense of belonging – some of
our predecessors in the world cultures have enriched us with reflections that can
still tackle this or other essential aspects of the matter. As far as this is the case, it
makes them ‘classics’, and no decent philosophy can be written without going
back, whenever appropriate, to the lessons of the classics, which is also a way to
highlight what is new or differently shaped in the problems we are confronted
with. As far as warping arbitrariness is avoided, we can feel free to pick up from
the classics the illuminating elements we may need in order to highlight a specific
new problem, without overstuffing our relationship with them with the study of
their whole system. This textbook tries to stick to these
self-imposed criteria in
our brief encounters with classics.
Finally, less easy to define, but important is the contribution
anthropology can give
to political philosophy. Both versions of anthropology are involved: philosophical
anthropology, the reflection on ‘the nature of man’ in its classical definition, and
cultural anthropology. The first one, present in all major political thinkers such as
Machiavelli, Hobbes and Kant, is nowadays rather a reflection on how that nature,
while containing constants in the relationship to nature and other beings, is also not
uninfluenced by the technical change and the related shift in our attitude towards
what is outside us, the world of objects. No philosophical
project can ignore this
The subjective side of politics
43
knowledge, or is condemned to assign tasks to or predict a future of an actor of
whom we do not even ask if her or his traits will resemble ours. On the other, cul-
tural anthropology can illuminate how differently political forms such as democ-
racy can impact on populations and cultures.
This excursus must end mentioning a loophole that, for architectural reasons,
will be filled in Chapter 4: it regards the relationship between politics and law,
or political philosophy and jurisprudence, same or similar stuff, divergent lenses
(epistemic devices) to look at it through. The essential nature of this relationship
is testified among other things by the fact that up to a hundred years ago political
philosophy did not exist as an academic discipline in most
European university sys-
tems, while the state, power and politics were topics taught in juridical fields such
as
Staatsrecht/state law or constitutional law.
More remarks on the epistemological status of political philosophy will come
in the next chapters in the framework of substantive topics, and particularly in
Chapter 10.
Notes
1 A discourse (
λόγος/
logos) about science or knowledge (επιςτήμη/
episteme).
2 In the first chapter, dedicated to Feuerbach, in particular section C, of
The German Ideol-
ogy, a manuscript written in 1845–1846 and first published in 1932 (Marx and Engels
1845).
3 The term is not of general and well-known use; my understanding of ‘reconstructive’
goes back to Bobbio – as explained in the first section of the
chapter on the state in Bob-
bio (1989, 44ff.) – rather than Habermas (on his use cf. https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/
Rational_reconstruction). ‘Analytical’ would not be perfectly adequate and engender
misunderstandings.
4 I shall abstain from the hopeless attempt to give clear definitions – dozens have been
advanced, often convoluted – of these terms. In my own language use, ethics points at
a rule-based behaviour of individuals and groups, while moral philosophy regards the
individual as such and looks at the intention rather than the behaviour. But my use does
not raise any claim of universalisation. More on this in Chapter 10.
5
A Theory of Justice (1999a) and
The Law of Peoples (1999b).
6 This translates Hegel’s
die Sache selbst, meaning the substantive issue or process under
investigation, whose dynamics he recommended to grasp and conceptualize instead of
insisting on one’s own principles and beliefs.
7 To have
a glimpse of this connection, one needs only to peer into the Table of Contents
and the Index of two influential works, such as Rawls’s
A Theory of Justice or Habermas’s
Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns (1981); in this latter work that relationship is more
explicitly worked out.
8
Hamlet, 1, 5. More fitting in our case is ‘our philosophy’, as the text reads in the First
Folio edition of Shakespeare’s works (1623).
9 In 1440 the Italian scholar Lorenzo Valla, a philosopher with high philological skills,
proved the document attesting the donation of territory made by the Roman emperor
Constantin in the fourth century to the Church was a fake, thus destroying the legiti-
macy of the papacy’s temporal power. His writing, however, was first published in Ger-
many after the Reformation.
10 When capitalised these words refer to the discipline, in
lower case to the real thing, the
relations
inter nationes.
11 Cf. Koselleck 1979.