182 Ethics
and politics
‘Between equals’ requires a more differentiated explanation. The equality meant
here is not matter-of-fact, but normative: I lend my support to others because I rec-
ognise them as equal in rights and dignity with myself, even if they are presently
unequal in the enjoyment of freedom and life chances. This is what distinguishes
solidarity, which is horizontal, from charity and philanthropy, which rather evoke
verticality. Also, solidarity as the fundamental category we are talking about cannot
be downsized to its meanings in social aid groups or in Catholic social thought.
Lastly and consequently, solidarity is seen here as a political virtue to be imple-
mented
by the state, not merely as a relationship between individuals.
Another question regards how to determine the perimeter of the equals: equal
in the local community, in the region or province, in the nation, in a civilisation,
or among humankind? To date, the current definitions of solidarity have pointed at
the (however defined) particular group as the sphere within which solidarity can
sensibly be expected to develop. This is well-known from its social history in the
West: the Freemasons in the Enlightenment, the clubs of the French revolutionar-
ies (before they started to send each other to the guillotine), the movements and
later the parties of the working class, including their
pledge to the international
solidarity of the proletarians, who, however, could not but massacre each other in
the trenches of the Great War. Yet can there be, contrary to this factual limitation,
a solidarity extended to the
whole of humankind, as it has been suggested over time
by humanists, pacifists and religious leaders? With an eye towards religious cleav-
ages and the upsurge of nations, this
suggestion or appeal was, with good reason,
regarded as politically ineffective. Things are now changing, as we have learned in
Chapter 7: with respect to its chances to survive global and lethal threats, and only
in this respect, humankind is becoming the dimension in which men and women
can experience solidarity with each other and the fellow humans of future genera-
tions.
6
This has normative relevance, but also – as explained above – an analytical
profile: without assuming that an initial form of the solidarity of humankind is at
work, especially
with regard to future humanity, it is difficult to explain the progress
made, for example, by a more reasonable climate policy at both a national and inter-
national level. Self-interest or security considerations do not explain everything
that is going on in politics, as we shall see in the Epilogue.
The relevance I am giving to solidarity comes from, among other things, the
puzzlement about the disappearance of its predecessor
fraternité from the glorious
triad ‘liberté égalité fraternité’ of the ‘ideas of ’89’ (
scil. 1789) – the brilliant career
of the two first partners notwithstanding. It looks like solidarity had been dismissed
or pushed to the sidelines due to three adverse and illusionary beliefs:
A. Social and political cohesion
is not a political issue, but a side effect of market
relationships.
B. Abstract deontological guidelines provided by ethics such as justice create
enough of political unity.
C. Cohesion is important, but it is entirely provided by living together in the
nation.