101
the Leviathan. In particular, I argue that direct action and networked organization activate
centrifugal power and, in so doing, have radically democratic potential.
Before moving onto
these issues, though, let me conclude with a final dilemma. Clastres
(1987, 218) concludes his seminal work with the following passage:
It is said that the history of peoples who have a history is the history of class
struggle. It might be said, with at least as much truthfulness, that the history of
peoples without history is the history of their struggle against the State.
An
important question remains, though. How could such societies have structured their political
life so as to avoid something they would never have seen: a powerful central state?
13
The answer
seems to be lost on Clastres, though it should have struck him clearly. As Graeber (2004, 22)
notes: “Amazonians were not entirely unaware of what elementary forms of state power might be
like – what it would mean to allow some men to give everyone else orders which could not be
questioned, since they were backed up by the threat of force.” Indeed, it is well documented that
many of the societies Clastres studied used rape as a tool to enforce gender roles and a certain
division of labor between men and women. Such a realization – one that
ought to dispel overly
romantic conceptions of Indian life – helps provide an answer to the obvious question noted
above.
Perhaps Amazonian men understand what arbitrary, unquestionable power,
backed by force, would be like because they themselves wield that sort of power
over their wives and daughters. Perhaps for that very reason they would not like
to see structures capable of inflicting it on them (
ibid
. 23).
The challenge that the Indian
presents to the Leviathan, therefore, is not simply a utopian
alternative. In presenting the politics of non-state societies my aim is not to idealize such people
nor is this a call to “go back” to a “primitive” way of living. Rather, my contention is that these
13
Such a question is not relevant to the subjects of Scott’s study who had (and have) clear exposure to the state, but
this question is relevant to Clastres who was studying communities that were far removed from state-making
projects.
102
societies offer a fundamentally different (though, of course, still problematic) way of confronting
the basic problems of human existence. They offer an answer that does not rely on the sovereign
state, that political
entity that seems so natural, so unavoidable and so necessary to us today.
While contemporary political theory seems to largely eschew Hobbes for more liberal thinkers,
at its core, much political theory, liberalism included, is still rooted in Hobbes’ statist solution
and his centripetal logic – a logic that can lead only to sovereignty. And, as I have endeavored to
show, sovereignty is fundamentally at odds with freedom.
For this reason, the ghost of the
Indian – the ghost of those who rejected the Leviathan and show us that there is another way –
ought to continue to haunt statist societies and political theorists alike.