Part II: Interventions in Democratic Theory
In Part II, I ask: How might the theoretical insights of the anti-authoritarian perspective
intervene in democratic theory? More specifically, if we: a) adopt a view of freedom as non-
domination, b) reject sovereignty in both its individual and state forms, c) and take on a
centrifugal logic of power, then where would that lead a corresponding account of radical
democracy? In short, what might an anti-authoritarian model of democracy look like?
To provide a partial answer to this question – and I will only be able to offer a partial
answer – I focus on two distinct, but related, anarchic social movement practices: direct action
and networked organization. My aim here is to walk a middle ground between two competing
approaches within the literature on anti-authoritarian visions of radical democracy. On the one
hand, some scholars abandon the more anarchic elements of anti-authoritarianism in their effort
to present a workable vision of radical democracy. On the other hand, other scholars maintain
the more anarchic elements of anti-authoritarianism, but do not connect these elements with the
literature on radical democracy or defend them on democratic grounds.
Perhaps the best recent statement of the former approach is Bookchin’s vision of an anti-
authoritarian democracy. While Bookchin (2007, 91-99) explicitly rejects the moniker of
anarchism in favor of “communalism” (due in large part to his perception that anarchism is too
sympathetic to individualism and too critical of democracy), his proposal still draws heavily on
aspects of anarchist thought. He traces the historical origins of communalism to the Paris
Commune of 1871 and sees it as a vision in which “virtually autonomous local communities are
26
loosely bound in a federation” (Bookchin 2007, 99). The concrete political proposal to emerge
out of communalism is “libertarian municipalism,” which calls for governing based on “popular
democratic assemblies” and addressing “community affairs on a face-to-face basis [and] making
policy decisions in a direct democracy” (
ibid.
101). While Bookchin’s vision has much in
common with the democratic vision I endorse, he remains wedded to more traditional modes of
decision-making. For him, the ancient Athenian
polis
and, more recently, the New England
townhall meeting are the prototypical democratic institutions (
ibid.
105; Biehl 1998, Ch. 3 and
4). In short, he remains tied to the old radically democratic ideal of the face-to-face assembly,
that I think critics of radical democracy are right to be skeptical about. The model of democracy
I articulate differs with this vision on at least two counts: 1) I do not equate radical democracy
with direct democracy and, in fact, argue for direct action, rather than direct democracy. 2) I
challenge the notion that decisions must be made through formalized channels (whether they be
direct or representative) at all. Instead, I maintain that decisions can
emerge
through networked
organization without ever being
made
in unified general assemblies. In essence, I see Bookchin
as foregrounding practices like general assemblies that are relatively easy to fold into a
democratic framework, but neglecting practices like direct action and networks that, while
central to anti-authoritarian movements and thinkers, are more problematic (but also, more
interesting) for democracy.
Other theorists who maintain a stronger attachment to these more anarchic elements,
however, do offer a “vision of an ideal (egalitarian, non-hierarchical) society, and a strategy for
achieving it, based on direct action and what Colin Ward has termed ‘spontaneous organization’”
(Ackelsberg 1997, 158). This body of anarchist theorizing bears closer resemblance to the
approach to radical democracy that I develop in the second half of the dissertation. For example,
27
Ward’s (1982) has argued for the potential for harmony to exist through complexity and for the
viability of “topless federations.” My aim in relation to this work to is to better connect these
concepts with democratic theory. While Bookchin develops a compelling vision of radical
democracy, he does so by prioritizing direct democracy over anarchism. In contrast, Ward
foregrounds anarchism, but neglects democracy. He develops a contemporary anarchist theory
of self-organization, but does not connect his vision to democracy or democratic norms. I
suggest that anarchic conceptions, such as direct action, “topless federations” and self-
organization, can be theorized in a democratic framework. In a sense, I build on the existing
literature by seeking to translate the ideas of anarchists and anti-authoritarians into the language
of democratic theory and, moreover, explain how anarchists might articulate their ideas in
(critical) relation to the concerns of democratic theory (e.g. ‘the people,’ legitimacy, and global
democracy). Doing so, I think, will help explain a way of theorizing a radical democracy that
eschews many of the usual trappings of state-centric democracy, while nonetheless constituting a
mode of action and organization that can be fairly conceptualized as democratic and defended on
democratic grounds.
In Chapter III, “The Democratic Potential of Direct Action,” I put direct action – a
practice in which people aim to accomplish their goals through their own activity (Sparrow n.d.)
– in conversation with democratic theory in an effort to uncover the tensions and affinities
between the two. Insofar as direct action involves a small segment of the
demos
directly
intervening in the lives of other citizens it could well be seen as a violation of democratic
principles and procedures. Despite this basic tension, however, there are important reasons to
defend the democratic potential of direct action. Namely, if radical democracy is,
fundamentally, a situation in which people have power, than practices that foster and enact
28
collective power have the potential to be democratic. I develop two forms of power that direct
action mobilizes: disruptive power and prefigurative power. In developing accounts of these two
forms of power, I challenge two reductions in contemporary democratic theory, one
characteristic of mainstream communicative democrats and the other characteristic of radical
democrats. First, because direct action is not primarily or exclusively a dialogical act, it
necessarily upsets the tendency to reduce democracy to deliberation and communication.
Whereas voting, lobbying, or writing – and even many forms of rallying or protesting – are
primarily oriented toward having voice, direct action is oriented toward having power. I contend
that the disruptive power of direct action, which halts institutional processes and interrupts the
activities of others, is democratic when it exposes, upsets, or reduces power inequalities and
makes real the political equality upon which democracy depends. Second, I use direct action’s
prefigurative power to challenge the reduction of democratic politics to a politics of resistance.
While direct action is most assuredly a practice that intervenes and disrupts, it is not just a
politics that resists, but also one that creates and prefigures. I show through an analysis of the
double-sided character of direct action a way to theorize a radical democratic politics that
transcends resistance and is capable of articulating and building an alternative society. My goal
in this chapter is to highlight the democratic potential of direct action, and to open the door to a
reconsideration of the role of power in a vibrant democratic politics. I conclude the chapter by
articulating a set of guidelines or criteria by which we might evaluate and/or amplify the
democratic potentials of direct action. Connecting this to the previous chapter, disruptive and
prefigurative power is democratic when it follows a centrifugal logic that spreads power and
creates spaces for others to exercise political freedom.
29
In Chapter IV, “Network Democracy,” I show one way in which social movements have
dispersed the power that direct action generates through the use of networks as a form of
organization.
If direct action constitutes a core democratic practice, I theorize networks as the
organizational framework that enables these relatively autonomous and local practices to fit
together in a much larger, more diffuse, and more powerful whole.
Just as elections are the link
between the practice of voting and a system of representative governance, networks are the
mechanism that connects direct actions together into a “system” of self-governance. However,
even though direct action is an exercise of power and even though the cumulative effect of these
actions through political networks can be considered a form of self-governance, the result need
not be a new form of authoritarian “rule over,” nor must this power constitute an emergent
sovereign. In contrast, I argue that networks are a social movement practice that functions to
both disperse power and to make self-governance possible without creating new forms of
sovereignty. To make this argument, I first present evidence for the possibility governance
without government through an examination of Ostrom’s (1990) work on self-governance of
common resources. She demonstrates that self-organization and self-governance – without
recourse to either the state or the market – is possible, in certain contexts. Her work, therefore, is
critical for thinking through the forms that self-governance might take. However, her work also
has serious limitations for assessing the capacity for self-governance in more diverse and diffuse
contexts. Not only are Ostrom’s case studies of successful self-governance based on relatively
small communities (rather than the transnational and global communities that comprise “the
multitude”), but they are often quite homogenous. And, it is precisely the facts of difference and
diversity that are the starting point for a range of contemporary democratic theories, and are
generally seen as presenting problems for democratic self-governance. Through a review of this
30
literature, I outline two competing responses to the fact of pluralism. The first response seeks to
overcome difference in order to form a unified
demos
capable of ruling. The second response
rejects the ideal of consensus and unanimity implicit in the first response, and proposes instead a
vision of democracy characterized by ongoing conflict and contestation. While there is much to
be admired in this approach, I contend that it offers little in the way of a positive prescription for
governing – or at least acting together – in the context of ineradicable agonism.
My aim in the second half of the chapter is to provide one response to this challenge, to
see what may come from an engagement between a theory of self-governance and a theory of
agonal democracy. The primary mechanism for fostering the goals of both – enabling self-
governance in the context of difference – is the network as a form of political organization. I
theorize networks as valuable because they enable
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |