that family is entitled upon request to have its baby’s United States passport
law, denying the Zivotofsky family’s religiously motivated request on the theory
whether the government of Israel is indeed sovereign over all of Jerusalem.
A closely divided Supreme Court ruled for the Executive. Regardless of
should instead address the matter squarely. For now, I turn to the extent to
both structural and individual rights issues posed by constitutional cases and
controversies.
Laurence H. Tribe, “Transcending the Youngstown Triptych: A Multidimensional Reappraisal
, at 103–4.
Foreign Relations Authorization Act Fiscal Year 2003, Pub. L. No. 107–228 § 214(d), 116 Stat.
the Tenure of Office Act of 1867 and to remove an executive officer without consent of the
lenging and would affect how the Court weighs those rights. A sufficiently wider lens may
have also considered the rights of classes of people beyond those in the same situation as little
Menachem Zivotofsky – for example, people who wanted to visit Israel but might have been
unable to do so if the Court had upheld the law and relations with Middle Eastern nations had
deteriorated as a result of the Court’s decision.
Soundings and Silences
45
2.3. Silences in the Constitution Generally versus
Silences in the Constitution’s Rules of Interpretation
I begin this part of the chapter by returning to one of the decisions I described
briefly in the autobiographical introduction, explaining what first led me
to use the “sounds of silence” as a frame through which to view the largest
constitutional questions: Griswold v. Connecticut, the Supreme Court’s 1965
invalidation of a state law criminalizing the use of contraceptives by married
couples.
145
Nothing in the Constitution’s text could be invoked to explain fully
why such a law could not withstand constitutional scrutiny.
In an early draft of the Court’s opinion striking the law down, Justice
Douglas sought to describe the conduct of a married couple to have unpro-
tected sexual intercourse as an exercise of the First Amendment right “peacea-
bly to assemble,” but Justice Black deftly responded that what he regularly did
with his wife of many years didn’t seem to either of them to be an instance of
peaceable assembly.
146
After abandoning that somewhat silly effort, Douglas settled on putting
the entire Bill of Rights into a jurisprudential Cuisinart, and emerged with a
mélange that treated a “right of marital privacy” as a mix of various “penum-
bras” of the First, Third, Fourth, Fifth, and Ninth Amendments.
147
Although
that Douglas effort was understandably derided by commentators as singularly
undisciplined to the point of being opaque, if not altogether incoherent, a
valid and indeed profound point lurked within the famed libertarian’s slap-
dash opinion.
148
The point was that those disparate amendments were not just
a sequence of unconnected limits on government authority over intimate per-
sonal choices. They were instead parts of a broader shield against totalitarian
government, a shield whose shape could not be specified with precision at any
given time, but whose existence could not be denied or even denigrated sim-
ply because it was not spelled out in detail anywhere in the Constitution’s text.
Douglas included the Ninth Amendment along with the others that he
poured into his verbal blender,
149
not pausing to recognize that he was mak-
ing a category error: the other amendments Douglas included each had a
substantive ambit referring to a particular kind of individual decision, or a
procedural ambit dealing with a specific sort of governmental practice. Unlike
the first eight amendments, the Ninth is a rule of construction, an overarch-
145
381 U.S. 479, 485–6 (1965).
146
Bernard Schwartz, The Unpublished Opinions of the Warren Court, 231–7 (1985).
147
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: