Soundings and Silences
35
that falls outside the points isolated.
87
Doing so would entail unjustifiably treat-
ing the absence of language expressly connecting the distinct constitutional
provisions as a “door-closing” silence, in the parlance of this chapter. The
alternative would be to treat the absence of connecting language linking the
provisions in question as a “door-opening” silence; an open invitation to bring
within constitutional control other kinds of government action that impinge
on the same set of overlapping values, even though falling outside the points
expressly isolated in the Constitution’s text.
As we will see in the section of this chapter dealing with rules of construction
or interpretation bearing on textual gaps or omissions, the text is in fact
not
entirely silent on that choice of approaches. But even if it were, it is impor-
tant to note that one option open to constitutional interpreters is to remain
silent about how to read the Constitution’s silence on the existence of a general
right to informational privacy beyond either the First Amendment or the Fourth.
That is exactly what the Supreme Court did in the NASA case, where the
majority opinion written by Justice Alito held that the government’s nonphys-
ical “probes” into the personal backgrounds of people seeking government
employment to work on improving the Hubble Telescope’s ability to conduct
deep space probes were not too invasive to comply with whatever unwritten
constitutional right of “informational privacy” might exist.
88
Concurring in
the result but dissenting from the majority’s approach, Justice Thomas and
the late Justice Scalia all but tore their hair out over the Court’s insistence
on leaving that question unanswered. To them, it seemed obvious that the
silence of the Constitution’s text on the existence of a right of informational
privacy had a door-closing character, given the fact that distinctive dimensions
of what such a right might be designed to protect were indeed picked out and
protected by a specific constitutional provision.
89
The place of silences in judicial opinions about the Constitution – a matter
on which the majority and the concurring justices in
NASA strongly disagreed –
will be taken up in a later section of this chapter, distinguishing silences
87
See Poe v. Ullman, 367 U.S. 497, 543 (1961) (Harlan, J., dissenting; citations omitted “[L]iberty
is not a series of isolated points . . . It is a rational continuum which, broadly speaking, includes
a freedom from all substantial arbitrary impositions and purposeless restraints.”
88
NASA, 562 U.S. at 159; see also
ibid.
, at 161 (Scalia, J., concurring in the judgment).
89
Ibid.
, at 161–2 (Scalia, J., dissenting). But right-leaning jurists are not the only ones who fall
into this trap. See e.g., Atwater v. City of Lago Vista, 532 U.S. 318, 336–40 (2001) (opinion
for the Court by Souter, J.; rejecting the view that the Due Process Clause “forbade peace
officers to arrest without a warrant for misdemeanors” on the ground that founders were not
concerned enough about the practice to prohibit it in the most relevant specific provision, the
Fourth Amendment.