The Invisible Constitution in Comparative Perspective



Download 4,63 Mb.
Pdf ko'rish
bet95/366
Sana18.08.2021
Hajmi4,63 Mb.
#150519
1   ...   91   92   93   94   95   96   97   98   ...   366
Bog'liq
The Invisible Constitution in Comparative Perspective by Rosalind Dixon (editor), Adrienne Stone (editor) (z-lib.org)

Jeffrey Goldsworthy

audience – whether lawyers or citizens – would attribute to the lawmakers, 

based on textual and contextual evidence available to them, and it might, 

therefore, differ from the actual subjective motives or purposes of the lawmak-

ers as individuals.

If this theoretical explanation of ‘objective’ purpose is rejected, some other 

explanation must be provided. It must somehow explain how legal purposes 

or values can be both created by acts of lawmaking, yet also objective in the 

sense of being independent of the lawmakers’ intentions or purposes. This is 

likely to be very difficult. We can at least understand how moral values might 

be objective even if, after philosophical analysis, we do not accept that they 

are. But that is because we do not think of moral values as being deliberately 

created by human beings, although they can be deliberately incorporated into 

a law by lawmakers. By contrast, laws are deliberately created by human law-

makers. How, then, can those laws have ‘objective’ purposes or values that are 

independent of the intentions and purposes of the people who made them? 

Even if a law incorporates an objective moral value, that can only be because 

the law in its context objectively manifests or evidences the lawmakers’ inten-

tion to do so. If the notion of an ‘objective purpose’ is supposed to have some 

other meaning, it should be regarded with deep suspicion: it is too metaphys-

ically queer to be believable.

Barak also claims that his interpretive theory may be consistent with some 

theories of pragmatics, albeit not Gricean or neo-Gricean theories.

142


 But 

instead of proving that claim, he calls for further research to develop such 

theories.

143


 This is unlikely to help him. The non-Gricean theories he men-

tions are similar to Gricean theories in that all treat pragmatic, or contextual, 

enrichment as revealing the actual author’s or speaker’s communicative inten-

tions. No theory of pragmatics of my acquaintance, in the field of linguistics 

or of philosophy of language, is built on the notion of an imaginary ‘ideal’ 

author.


4.7.  Conclusion: Inexplicit Content and  

Lawmakers’ Intentions

The literal meaning of a sentence may have logical implications or entail-

ments. But almost all implicit and implied content depends on some ingredi-

ent in addition to the words of the text, and as different theories of pragmatics 

all agree, this can only be contextual evidence of the author’s communicative 

142 

Barak,Supra note 130, 71.



143 

Ibid.


, 72–3.


 

The Implicit and the Implied in a Written Constitution 

145


intentions, including evidence of his or her purpose in communicating. We 

have seen how determining even the express meaning of a written constitu-

tion can require contextual enrichment, because (inter alia) of the inclusion 

of indexicals, relational and ambiguous terms and ellipses. The references of 

relational and ambiguous terms cannot be determined, and ellipses identified 

and filled in, other than by contextual evidence of authorial intention. In the 

case of ellipses, somewhat paradoxically, express meaning includes inexplicit 

content.


In addition, a constitution’s implied meaning can include implicatures 

and implicit assumptions that can also be revealed only through contextual 

enrichment. Implicatures depend on evidence of the author’s intention to 

communicate something by implication.

144

 To speak of an implicit assumption 



which was taken for granted, is to speak of what the author took for granted. 

Texts cannot meaningfully be said to take anything for granted, at least not 

if their meaning is confined to literal meaning, severed from their authors’ 

intentions. Even fabricated implications, which lawyers oddly describe as 

being ‘read into’ or ‘implied into’ laws, are usually justified in terms of what is 

necessary to fulfil the lawmakers’ intentions or purposes.

145

For these reasons, a constitution protects by implication ‘structural’ princi-



ples or values, such as representative democracy, federalism, the rule of law 

and the separation of powers, only if and insofar as contextual as well as textual 

evidence suggests that its makers had the requisite intention or purpose. This 

is so whether or not the implication is a genuine one ascertained by clarifying 

interpretation, or a fabricated one inserted by rectifying interpretation.

A major challenge for anyone who rejects intentionalism or originalism  

is to provide a plausible alternative analysis of these commonplace aspects  

of legal meaning and interpretation. I am not aware of any serious attempt  

to do so. Moreover, if it is true that they can plausibly be explained only in 

terms of inferences from text and context to the lawmaker’s probable com-

municative intentions, then notwithstanding the difficulties of explaining  

the nature of collective intentions – a promising philosophical research 

program that has only recently begun – we have no practicable alternative  

other than continuing to interpret constitutions on the assumption that such 

intentions exist.

146


144 

See Section 

4.4.2

.

145 



See Section 

4.5


.

146 


See also Carston, Supra note 34, 25, quoting Stephen Neale.


146

A constitution – considered as a visible, written legal text – exists within a 

broader social and political context. This chapter argues that, to a significant 

extent, it is this context that gives the constitution and the laws made under 

it whatever legal force they have; but that this context is not (and cannot be) 

contained within it. Every constitution, therefore, has a crucial yet invisible 

aspect.

1

The argument of the chapter is a philosophical one. Its goal, however, is 



not purely philosophical. Rather, it is to show that considerations of analytic 

jurisprudence, and analytic philosophy more generally, suggest a sociological 

conclusion, namely, that each constitutional order must be its own particular 

thing, by virtue of its distinctive invisible elements.

5.1.  Anti-positivism and the Invisibility of the  

Constitution

The claim stated in the opening paragraph of this chapter is easy to make 

out for an adherent of an anti-positivist, more-or-less Dworkinian account of 

law that identifies the law not primarily with the content of and requirements 


Download 4,63 Mb.

Do'stlaringiz bilan baham:
1   ...   91   92   93   94   95   96   97   98   ...   366




Ma'lumotlar bazasi mualliflik huquqi bilan himoyalangan ©hozir.org 2024
ma'muriyatiga murojaat qiling

kiriting | ro'yxatdan o'tish
    Bosh sahifa
юртда тантана
Боғда битган
Бугун юртда
Эшитганлар жилманглар
Эшитмадим деманглар
битган бодомлар
Yangiariq tumani
qitish marakazi
Raqamli texnologiyalar
ilishida muhokamadan
tasdiqqa tavsiya
tavsiya etilgan
iqtisodiyot kafedrasi
steiermarkischen landesregierung
asarlaringizni yuboring
o'zingizning asarlaringizni
Iltimos faqat
faqat o'zingizning
steierm rkischen
landesregierung fachabteilung
rkischen landesregierung
hamshira loyihasi
loyihasi mavsum
faolyatining oqibatlari
asosiy adabiyotlar
fakulteti ahborot
ahborot havfsizligi
havfsizligi kafedrasi
fanidan bo’yicha
fakulteti iqtisodiyot
boshqaruv fakulteti
chiqarishda boshqaruv
ishlab chiqarishda
iqtisodiyot fakultet
multiservis tarmoqlari
fanidan asosiy
Uzbek fanidan
mavzulari potok
asosidagi multiservis
'aliyyil a'ziym
billahil 'aliyyil
illaa billahil
quvvata illaa
falah' deganida
Kompyuter savodxonligi
bo’yicha mustaqil
'alal falah'
Hayya 'alal
'alas soloh
Hayya 'alas
mavsum boyicha


yuklab olish