Russell A. Miller
given. But the Court has yoked itself to a three-part formula that gives its work
in this context the feeling of objectivity and scientific inquiry. In the first step,
the Court begins by defining the scope of the asserted constitutional protec-
tion. This, for example, requires the Court to answer the question “to whom
or what does the basic right apply?” In the second step the Court assesses
whether there has been a direct or indirect encroachment upon the protecta-
ble scope of the basic right. In the third step the Court determines whether an
encroachment on the basic right has been justified. This, in turn, requires the
Court to follow one of two systematic paths, one for rights that can be limited
by statute,
174
and another for rights that are absolute.
175
Each of these tracks
involves a distinct, systematized assessment.
The central component of step three (the determination whether an
encroachment is justified) is the application of the proportionality principle
for which the Court is well-known.
176
The proportionality principle might be
characterized as an open-ended balancing test that gives the justices unchecked
and dangerously subjective discretion to assign “weight” to competing interests
and to reach conclusions on the basis of an unsystematic balancing exercise.
177
There is some truth in this critique. But the criticism should grapple with
the Constitutional Court’s highly methodical approach to proportionality
analysis. In fact, in the system developed by the Court, the proportionality
principle involves balancing or weighing only as the last of four steps in the
analysis.
178
Before determining whether measures that encroach upon basic
rights are proportional to the benefits they are intended to produce, the Court
first examines whether the measures are legitimate, suitable, and necessary.
174
Kommers, Supra note 13, 857 (“[a] close look at the Basic Law discloses an interesting hierar-
chy of rights. Some are cast in unqualified language”).
175
Ibid.
(“[a]ll other rights are conditional, and they fall into three categories. First are those
rights which can only be limited by the terms of the Basic Law itself . . . The second category of
conditional rights are those whose contours are to be defined by law . . . Finally, certain rights
may be restricted by the ‘general laws’. The reference here is to the general provisions of the
civil and criminal code”).
176
See e.g., Dieter Grimm, “Proportionality in Canadian and German Constitutional Jurispru-
dence” (2007) 57 University of Toronto Law Journal 383.
177
See Vicki C. Jackson, “Ambivalent Resistance and Comparative Constitutionalism: Opening
Up the Conversation on ‘Proportionality’, Rights, and Federalism” (1999) 1 Journal of Consti-
tutional Law 583, 603–4 (quoting William Stuntz as asserting “[t]here is no nonarbitrary way
to arrive at the proper legal rules, no way to get to sensible bottom lines by something that
looks and feels like legal analysis. Whether proportionality review is lodged in appellate or trial
courts, the only way to do it is to do it, to decide that this sentence is too great but not that one.
There is no metric for determining right answers, no set of analytical tools that defines what a
given sentence ought to be”).
178
Robert Alexy, “Constitutional Rights, Balancing, and Rationality” (2003) 16 Ratio Juris 131, 135.
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |