ago in a backward but developing country whose nascent legal systems were offshoots of the
Common Law. If we measure success by continuance over time, a pair of Common Law
countries, Canada [1867] and Australia [1900], generated the other most ‘successful’ constitu-
tional democracies ... In stark contrast, Latin American countries – all consumers of the Civil
Law – have changed their constitutions with a regularity analogous to that with which modern
farmers rotate crops. Moreover, as was also the case in Mejei Japan and the Russian, German,
and Austro-Hungarian empires, these ‘constitutions’ have sometimes made scant pretense of
trying to establish regimes that were either democratic or limited. And when constitutional
democracy was the objective in other Civil-Law nations, as in Germany and Poland after
World War I, the resulting polities were often unstable, providing only one phase in a
sequence that quickly cycled back to authoritarian rule”).
498
Russell A. Miller
Murphy concluded, involves a “supple pragmatism over tight logic” that is
inherent in the “messiness of constitutional politics.”
88
Murphy is not the only scholar to remark on the correlation between the
common law tradition and constitutionalism. Others have noted that the
non-textual balancing tests and constitutional standards that have developed
in constitutional jurisprudence are more akin to the common law than to
the practice of any other legal tradition. David Strauss, for example, argued
that “it is the common law approach . . . that best explains, and best justifies,
American constitutional law today.”
89
Henry Monaghan was so persuaded by
the linkages that he fashioned a theory of the “constitutional common law”
that accounts for the law constitutional courts develop, either through author-
itative constitutional interpretation, or as a “substructure of substantive, pro-
cedural, and remedial rules drawing their inspiration and authority from” the
constitution.
90
It is easy to see why this uncontroversial description of the work
of constitutional courts might be seen as closely allied with the common law
tradition. In fact, Monaghan’s thesis has gained adherents in the generation
since he proposed it. More recently, Abigail Moncrieff once again confirmed
that “the judicial habit of enforcing broad constitutional norms” was precisely
the “feature of modern constitutionalism that Henry Monaghan famously
88
Ibid.
89
David A. Strauss, “Common Law Constitutional Interpretation” (1996) 63
University of Chi-
cago Law Review 877, 879. The notion that American constitutional law is a common law
system has occurred to many. See e.g., Frederick Schauer, “Is the Common Law?” (1989)
77 California Law Review 455, 470 and note 4; Paul Brest, “The Misconceived Quest for the
Original Understanding” (1980) 60 Boston University Law Review 204, 228–9, note 90 (cited
in note 4) (identifying “adjudication” and the “common law method” with “nonoriginalist
strategies of constitutional decision-making”). Harry H. Wellington has endorsed what he
describes as a “common-law method of constitutional interpretation.” Harry H. Wellington,
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: