Mouffe and Agonal Democracy
Whereas Rawls and Habermas see in difference a threat to democracy, Mouffe sees their
proposed solution to difference – consensus or unanimity – as the real problem. “To negate the
ineradicable character of antagonism and to aim at a universal rational consensus – this is the real
threat to democracy” (Mouffe 2000, 22).
35
The condition of pluralism is the very condition of
democracy, so efforts to suppress that difference are, at their core, anti-democratic. For Mouffe
35
This is not the only central difference between these thinkers, of course. For instance, whereas, Habermas sees
liberalism and democracy as mutually constitutive, Mouffe sees them as fundamentally in tension.
169
(2000, 15-16) we must accept that “conflict and division are inherent to politics and that there is
no place where reconciliation could be definitely achieved as the full actualization of the unity of
‘the people.’” The challenge for democratic politics then is
not
to find the right procedure –
whether that be “public reason” or “communicative action” – for achieving consensus. Instead,
democratic politics should be aimed at enabling and fostering contestation over competing values
and competing interpretations of those values. Though Mouffe argues that “antagonism” is
basically “ineradicable,” she contends that the aim of democratic politics is to transform it.
While antagonism occurs between enemies, agonism occurs between adversaries – though we
disagree with adversaries we recognize their right to defend their views. The aim of Mouffe’s
vision, therefore, is to enable conflict, but transform conflict from antagonism to agonism (
ibid
.
102-103).
While agonal democrats like Mouffe do
valorize
conflict as a necessary element of
democratic politics, I think, they are wrongly viewed as
glorifying
conflict. It is not that conflict
is the highest aim of democratic politics, but rather that in the context of pluralism it is
unavoidable and, hence democratically necessary. “In a democratic polity, conflicts and
confrontations, far from being a sign of imperfection, indicate that democracy is alive and
inhabited by pluralism” (Mouffe 2000, 34). Attempts to permanently resolve such disagreements
through the achievement of consensus do not constitute the pinnacle of democracy, but its
annulment. They are a flight from democratic politics, as such.
What is misguided is the search for a final rational resolution…Such a search
should be recognized for what it really is, another attempt at insulating politics
from the effects of the pluralism of value…Democratic theory should renounce
those forms of escapism and face the challenge that the recognition of the
pluralism of values entails” (Mouffe 93).
170
More fundamentally, and in a way, I take this as Mouffe’s central point, attempts to reach
consensus in a pluralistic world are, fundamentally, exercises of power. Perhaps as a result of
their emphasis on process and procedure, what deliberative democrats miss, or at least under-
theorize, is “the moment of ‘decision’” (Mouffe 2000, 130). Deliberative democrats “are unable
to recognize that bringing a deliberation to a close always results from a
decision
which excludes
other possibilities” (Mouffe 2000, 105). For Mouffe, we should acknowledge the “moment of
decision” for what it is: an expression of power.
Consensus in a liberal-democratic society is – and will always be – the expression
of hegemony and the crystallization of power relations…To deny the existence of
such a moment of closure, or to present [it] as dictated by rationality or morality,
is to naturalize what should be perceived as a contingent and temporary”
hegemony (Mouffe 2000, 49).
36
It is not that Mouffe thinks we should avoid, resist or put off the “moment of decision,” for this
is an essential part of politics. Thus, it is a mistake to view Mouffe’s agonal democracy as
simply an argument for perpetual contestation. Rather, she pays more attention to the “moment
of decision” – the culminating act of governance – than deliberative democrats do. What she
argues is that these moments, the very products of governance, always “entail an element of
force and violence that can never be eliminated” (
ibid
. 130). At some point a decision has to be
reached, and since consensus is an empirical (for Habermasians) or conceptual (for Mouffe)
impossibility, a decision will be taken without consensus. Thus, there is no possibility of
36
Mouffe’s view that any consensus or decision is a mere “expression of hegemony and the crystallization of power
relations” leaves her open to the criticism that she offers no standard for evaluating whether certain instances of
consensus – or certain power relations – are better than others. Benhabib (1996, 78), for example, says: “I think it is
fair to ask whether the radical democratic theories [including that elaborated by Mouffe]…allow for a coherent
theory of rights such as would protect both basic rights and liberties for all, and defend minority rights against the
tyranny of the majority.” Because Mouffe emphasizes the contingency of existing political arrangements – and that
such arrangements are little more than manifestations of power relations – Benhabib contends that it cannot defend a
system of rights, which liberal and deliberative democrats see as enabling the very contestation Mouffe valorizes.
Agonal democracy is a highly unstable form and perhaps contains within it the seeds of its own destruction insofar
as it does not offer a standard for excluding forms of pluralism that are anti-pluralistic, or forms of contention that
seeks to eradicate future contention.
171
achieving a non-coercive consensus. Agreement, from this angle, is an act of violence. Though
expressed in a somewhat different way, Maeckelbergh (2009, 32) argues that it is precisely this
concern that motivates the alter-globalization movement to resist state-centric forms of
democracy:
[A]s long as democracy is defined as a system of majority rule it necessarily
requires an apparatus of coercive force…This relationship between democracy
and violence is part of what leads many movement actors to question the
desirability of democracy and to insist… [on] a radically different form.
The rejection of the ideal consensus or agreement – regardless of the procedures for
attaining it – does not spell the end of democracy, though, for either Mouffe or alter-
globalization movement activists. Rather it points us toward a democracy not oriented toward
consensus. For Mouffe, this means an orientation toward contestation– an impetus to question
the existing consensus and problematize them as moments of closure. Surely, alter-globalization
movements and many other social movements, as well, agree on this point. However, I think
movement practices suggest that they want to do more than that. Not only do they contest
existing decisions, but they also strive to develop models of decision-making that minimize, if
not avoid entirely, the coercion and violence that the politics of consensus entails.
37
In other
words, I would like to argue that social movements – through the practice of networked
organization – reformulate what the “moment of decision” itself looks like. What if the
“moment of decision” could incorporate different decisions, specifically, decisions to act
differently? Rather than thinking about decision as necessarily involving agreement, consensus
and unanimity, networks enable people to act together, while acting differently.
37
Though, as we shall see, some contemporary social movements have remained wedded to consensus through the
model of the “general assembly.” I will argue later in the chapter that this is the wrong move and that movement
actors should find ways of implementing a networked form of organization, even when sharing a common space.
172
If Rawls and Habermas suppress difference in order to govern, and Mouffe enables
differences but does not offer a more liberatory model of governing, my aim is to find something
of a middle ground between these two approaches – or, perhaps, a radical alternative to them.
On the one hand, I want to take difference and pluralism as a given and see the conflict that such
facts generate as an unavoidable component of democracy; in short, I agree with Mouffe, that
consensus is an impossibility in a democratic context. On the other hand, I do not want to
abandon the task of governance or fail to distinguish between better and worse “moments of
decision,” since they are all necessarily mere functions of power. Rather, I argue that social
movement actors develop and employ practices that help individuals and groups work together
despite their differences – to simultaneously cooperate and act while “resisting unity through
networks” (Maeckelberg 2009, 188). In this way, I hope to show that networks avoid the
problems associated with both Rawls and Habermas, i.e. the way both seek to suppress
difference. They neither exclude persons from participation at the outset – indeed, the
boundaries of the networked are blurry and fluid, perhaps even to a fault – nor do they require a
consensus or even agreement as an end product. At the same time, networks offer a more
liberatory way of thinking about “the moment of decision” and challenge of self-governance
insofar as they make it possible for people to act together, while retaining their differences. We
can, therefore, avoid the conclusion that consensus is necessary in order to coordinate, or that
agreement is necessary in order to act together. Networks offer a model of self-governance
appropriate for contexts characterized by difference, diversity, and pluralism.
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |