party) and conferring her or him an imperative mandate. This does ordinarily not
happen, while her or his conformity to the mandate could also hardly be checked,
for legal and technical reasons.
The strong reason is that, confronted with policy making, the electorate, espe-
cially the swinging wings that do and undo majorities, more often than not chooses
to support its immediate self-interest, disregarding the likely needs of people too far
in space (the poor of the world, say) and time (future generations) who cannot
make their voice heard. The presently much lamented short-termism of democratic
politics has one of its roots here. Giving immediate, daily policy-making power to
the broad electorate would block innovation and reform, which are often advanced
by small avantgardes without the stable support of the majority.
On account of these two reasons combined, the idea of representative bodies
being replaced by this version of e-democracy with daily or weekly voting looks
very much like a nightmare, a Nineteen Eighty-Four with a collective and imper-
sonal Virtual Big Brother.
13
In addition to the previous considerations, the learning
process taking place among active citizens, politicians and bureaucrats in the debate
occurring in public opinion and parliament is worth being preserved and not dis-
carded in favour of the fictional competence of every isolated individual to shape
policy. Even in mature democracies the web seems to have become primarily the
venue used by parts of the population to vent their dominating approach to politics,
that is anger and resentment against rulers and fellow citizens as well, all spiced with
falsehoods, unfounded claims and inflammatory language. Traditional voting has
been also influenced by these attitudes, as in the 2016 Brexit referendum in the UK.
In other words, the cook whom Lenin in 1917 wanted to make eligible for run-
ning the country – we met her already in Chapter 1 – would have led it into disaster
much swifter than the Communist regime did, and extreme egalitarianism is, in gen-
eral, not to be taken seriously in its claims, because of its counter-intentional effects
(the Russian Revolution rather produced a self-perpetuating bureaucratic elite) and
because it denies the specificity and complexity of political activity. In the practise
of democratic countries, cooks or actors or grocers or professors of both sexes have
become eligible for public office only once they have learned the art of politics on
the field – as politicians, not as defined by their former profession or social status.
These arguments in favour of representative democracy resonate in part with
those against the tyranny of the majority made by classical liberalism, eminently by
Government and democracy 91
Alexis de Tocqueville (1805–1859) in his masterwork De la démocratie en Amérique/
Of Democracy in America (1835). Focusing on the downsides of democracy, we should
rather direct our attention to recent experiences such as the deterioration of demo-
cratic processes due to the overwhelming pressure stemming from the massive spec-
tacularization of politics or to what the Columbia scholar of democracy Giovanni
Sartori has dubbed ‘videocracy’. This all comes down to political will-formation and
communication being subjugated under the logic of televised entertainment, far
beyond the inevitable percentage of theatrical self-presentation that already played a
role in the Greek agoras. Another distorting factor lies in the polarisation of political
conflict that occurs in some countries, most notably in the USA, with electoral cam-
paigns whose core has been summarised as ‘who hates who’. This seems to weaken
or to erode the political identity of the citizens, which is in a democracy more vital
than elsewhere since more than others this regime must be able – as we have seen –
to rely on a universally shared belief in certain values and principles.
* * *
We have thus examined the presently more influential downsides of democracy
that emerge on the subjective side of politics. They converge in creating the ter-
rain for one of the two greatest dangers surrounding democracy itself: populism, the
other danger being its low efficacy in policy making, as we shall see. By populism
I mean the belief in the ‘people’ being the sole owner not just of sovereignty, but
of any actual power, the touting of this entity against any limitation set by liberal-
democratic institutions and the proclamation of its morally superior rights against
any elite.
14
Since the beginning of the twentieth century onwards, universal suffrage
made the masses of voters co-protagonists of political life, both a rightist and a leftist
populism
15
have popped up time and again in most countries, with the exception of
countries with previous and engrained autocratic traditions such as China and, to a
lesser extent, Russia; we cannot possibly explore here the historical phenomenol-
ogy of this attitude, nor can we discuss the epistemological problems arising from a
notion that, while indispensable, is sometimes overstretched.
Populist movements and initiatives can be revealing signals of social pathologies,
such as the sky-rocketing income inequality within most countries, and political
failures in managing the ordinary citizen’s problems. Populism as a political project
can be dangerous for the domestic democratic stability, leading not only to the de-
legitimation of the institutions protecting fundamental rights by the rule of law, but
also to the undoing of democratic peace as well as international peace, since right-
leaning populism in particular mostly comes paired with eruptions of nationalism.
Not to forget is the tendency to authoritarian leadership or caesarism residing in
the ‘people’ of populism, which can by its very nature be led only by bosses and
demagogues adept at creating political myths and distortions and using the media
for the mobilisation of masses.
Populism would not represent such a relevant threat to democracy if it did not
happen to re-emerge
16
in a time marked by what we may call the objective downsides
of democracy, which are obviously interconnected with the subjective ones, their
92 How politics works
distinction only being analytical. In Western countries, but not only here, the dif-
ficulties in reacting to the effects of globalisation, in particular (youth) unemploy-
ment, job precariousness and bad jobs with low pay go hand-in-hand with the
demise of welfare entitlements and the weakening of social safety nets – along with
the loss of social capital highlighted by Robert Putnam (Putnam 1993, 2000) for
the USA, but not limited to America. Islamist terrorism and its grasp on second
generation immigrants, along with the never-ending wave of new migrants have
grown into an additional problem, along with the constitutional questions aris-
ing from the inevitably enhanced security regimes. Also, whatever the real grasp
of these phenomena, renewed talks of secular stagnation and of an emerging and
job-cutting Fourth Industrial Revolution add to the subjective disorientation of
citizens. This, along with the justified ‘indignation’
17
caused by rising inequality, is
the breeding ground for one or the other shape of populism, whose dangerousness
lies in its ability to pick up existing and justified elements of protest against gov-
ernments while proposing to tear down the institutional safety nets protecting any
politics based on rational debate and shared rules of the game.
On the whole, populism seems to make the worst out of the ambivalent notion
of ‘the people’ that lies at the core of democracy: one more reason to abandon this
hypostasised notion along with all the surrounding rhetoric and put instead in place
‘the citizens’. But it is also true that the present state of affairs in democracies – not to
mention some of the other troubles we will address later on – seems to provide fuel
for the populist fires that erupt time and again in several countries. As long as this
fuel is not neutralised by redesigning democracy, there is little chance that the fires
cease to erupt. One could even ask if the type of mentality (made of manichaeis-
tic simplifications, disregard for complex arguments, rancour and self-righteousness)
prevailing in populist electorates is not going to occupy more and more minds,
voiding democracy of its meaning and values. On this front the only proposal so
far is to complement or (in radical formulations) replace the voting procedures of
representative democracy with deliberations involving all stakeholders, in which rea-
sonable arguments capable of finding solutions adequate to the common good are
exchanged rather than relying on bargaining or mediating between positions based
on self-interest. Participants in deliberative democracy
– as its theorists intend by draw-
ing on Habermas’s thought – present their arguments relying on the ‘claims of valid-
ity’ that are common to any linguistic exchange among competent citizens. Those
theorists have meanwhile set out a large literature containing models of deliberative
democracy that seem to satisfy their normative perfectionism rather than to tackle
the troubles of democratic regimes around the world. More helpful for the future
of democracy among citizens who are a mix of income maximizers (be the actor a
millionaire or a low-income pensioner) and partisan political philosophers are the
experiments of deliberative processes in local communities, which can be in this way
more broadly involved in consultations that prepare for the formal decision making
of representative bodies such as city councils. In these cases the quality of democracy
is enhanced, with regard to both the procedure and the substantive outcomes –
policies that are often better than those resulting from mere voting. Also, the range
of deliberative democracy remains obviously limited, as it cannot apply to, say, the
Government and democracy 93
national budget or foreign policy decisions. Overblown confidence in it is not a
good service to what it could do for the troubled democracy of the present time.
* * *
Do these very cautious and demythologizing views about democracy mean that
this book identifies with the famous definition formulated by Joseph Schumpeter?
the democratic method is that institutional arrangement for arriving at polit-
ical decisions in which individuals acquire the power to decide by means of
a competitive struggle for the people’s vote.
(Schumpeter 1942, 269)
This definition is not only elitist, in the sense that it views politics mainly as a
business among smart and powerful individuals, but also peers into it with eco-
nomic notions such as competition for a sought-after scarce good – the major-
ity of votes. The definition is a pinnacle of political realism and has, ever since its
first formulation in 1942, caused rejection as well as attraction. It comes closer
to how democracy really functions than its definition as ‘government of/by/for
the people’, which taken literally materialises nearly nowhere – also because of
the ambiguity of the ‘people’ notion explained above. On the other hand, also in
Schumpeter’s formula the people or the generality of citizens remains the bearer
of sovereignty or ultimate power, which confers the (derived, secondary) power to
make policy decisions on the individuals (or parties) that have gained more votes.
In an ironical sense the formula has regained validity: while in the decades after the
last World War, power was rather conferred upon parties, it is now again in many
countries the individual leader, along with her or his staff, to play – in the so-called
personalization of politics – the main role in the electoral game and the formula-
tion of policies. The demise of the party format as the pivot of the political process
in democracies has degenerative effects on the latter, as it deprives political decision
making of an orderly connection to problems and disfunctions in the society as well
as protest or new ideas among citizens.
A concluding remark: the image of democracy resulting from this chapter
focuses on it as a procedure, though the substantive implications of liberal democ-
racy have been also highlighted. In a procedural view on democracy we are in
the good and large company of the likes of thinkers as different from each other
as Joseph Schumpeter, Hans Kelsen (1881–1973), Norberto Bobbio and Jürgen
Habermas – to mention just a few. In the political history of the nineteenth and
twentieth century, however, to be ‘democratic’ has mostly implied not just loyalty
to a method, but also a position left from the centre, implying wealth redistribution,
job creation and protection, more rights for women and minorities – in a word,
a preference for equality over liberty. The word still keeps much of its symbolical
or label-like function, in America as well as in Europe and elsewhere. It has sur-
vived the misuse done to it in the former Communist bloc, as ‘democratic’ was the
official standard definition of the countries that were not allowed to claim to have
94 How politics works
attained ‘socialism’ as the leading power, the Union of Soviet Socialist Republics,
did. The name of the Democratic People’s Republic of Korea is a remnant of those
times, in which a further, now largely vanished dichotomy – substantive vs. formal
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |