114
or medical means should be viewed with
special
suspicion. One can wonder why, if
it coincidentally so happened that either a sudden
and dramatic life experience, a
month of practicing qigong or a psychotherapy session produced exactly the same
physiological changes in brain function (and resulted in the same profile of
personality changes), we should consider this ‘natural’ way of personality change
less suspicious than the changes that result from DBS. So Schechtman’s account is
open to charges of arbitrarily treating interventions as problematic without defining
what kinds of means are problematic, nor giving convincing arguments as to why
they are problematic.
A more charitable reading of the argument presented in Schechtman (2009) may get
at some of our intuitions as to why a change of values, beliefs or character traits
following
DBS may be troubling; it is not that DBS is problematic in virtue of it
being a technological means of affecting change, but rather because the intervention
belongs to a class of change-affecting events which are
difficult to make sense of
within a personal narrative
. Perhaps a shift in views after intense qigong practice or
a life-shaking event could be equally problematic, if unaccompanied by reflection
and integration of the new stance towards life – including giving epistemic and
genealogical reasons for this stance.
Moreover, even if DBS would undermine a person’s identity-narrative, there is no
reason to think that biomedically induced disruptions in identity-narratives are
irreparable. If a person could re-invent a narrative following
severe personality
changes due to head trauma, there is no obvious reason that a person who
undergoes DBS could not. Thus, rather than pointing to a DBS-induced identity
dead-end, Schechtman’s account highlights that the integration of personality
changes into person’s understanding of themselves may be challenging. The
challenging nature of such changes has been highlighted in some research on
patients' perspect
ives (Agid et al. 2006, Shupbach et al. 2006).
However, the
question about the moral weight of the risk of such identity
crisis or narrative
disruption remains unanswered.
Another interpretation of Schechtman’s (2009) objection may relate to the intuition
that the values, desires and beliefs which can be causally traced back to DBS
somehow lack anchoring in the persons own life. When she argues that
‘his [the
115
patient’s] current passions and interests – the things he takes as reasons – were
caused by manipulation of his brain’ (2009, p. 85) this can be interpreted either as
referring to the new values not being truly his own (a concern perhaps better
understand as a concern about authenticity) or being somehow baseless,
epistemically unjustified.
The
latter claim represents
a related, yet separate worry about the epistemic
justification of new values, beliefs and character traits after DBS. This epistemic
problem could be especially important if new values, beliefs and character were
less
justified than the previous ones. However, in situations when previous justifications
were weak (e.g. a depressed patient who believes that she worthless
as a result of
trauma), justified in the past but not the present (‘My life is full of emotional pain’
for a formerly depressed patient) or equally as well or poorly justified as a new
belief (e.g. I’m a conservative because my father was a conservative, I’m a liberal
because that is my fancy after DBS), the degree of justification of the beliefs does
not change. This worry, however, is more closely related to Schechtman’s reality
constraint on identity-narratives and opens up an altogether different discussion.
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: