80
distinction between viable and not viable and valid and invalid
medical diagnoses
would help the essentialism. Firstly, it is unclear what viability means according to
Conrad (2007) and how it is different from validity. Perhaps it means
‘reasonability’ or ‘usability’ or ‘usefulness’ in the given social context, since
Conrad refers to the distinction understood in social constructivist terms; yet it is
still unclear how that would impact the way sociological
researchers go about
choosing which diagnosis to investigate and how to investigate them. Parens (2011)
suggests that in practice researchers tend to implicitly use the valid/invalid
distinction, since sociologists do not investigate all viable diagnoses but rather pick
and choose which diagnoses to investigate as cases of medicalization.
Another thread running through many objections to medicalization refers to the
intuition that usual and normal human traits should not be understood as medical
problems, even if they negatively impact wellbeing. The problem with the critics’
narrow conception of the goals of medicine that this usually entails – whether
explicitly or inexplicitly – is some notion of
normal
or
species-typical
functioning
(Boorse, 1977; Daniels, 1985; Sabin and Daniels, 1994), usually used normatively.
However, the attempts to construe the notions of health and disease with reference
to those concepts are riddled with problems (see: Agich, 1983; Engelhardt, 1986;
Fulford, 1989; Harris 2007). Moreover, even if we could base our notions of health
and disease on those distinctions, it is far from obvious that the protection of health
is the only ‘proper’ goal of medicine – doctors
typically perform organ
transplantations, advise about contraception (which is plausibly understood as
disrupting normal functioning of the organism for the benefit of preventing
unwanted pregnancy), advise employers about their workers’ health, perform
immunisations, etc. (Harris, 2007; Pacholczyk, 2011). Moreover,
doctors perform
amputations and brain lesions to ameliorate problems and avert danger to health or
life (hardly, however, by restoring normal physiological function), prescribe aspirin
that keeps blood clots from forming by interfering with the ‘normal’ production of
thromboxine (keeping blood clotting below the average), prescribe bisphosphonate
to prevent osteoporosis often occurring in older people by modifying the usual
activity of bone cells, and prescribe hormone pills to reduce menstrual bleeding .
81
Thus, the generally accepted toolkit of medical professionals includes interventions
which 1) do not attempt to restore health or prevent disease at all (e.g. providing
birth control), 2) do not restore species typical-functioning yet are typically seen as
treatment/prevention of a disease (e.g. dietary advice to ensure better health and
longevity). This suggests that relying on a narrow concept
of the proper goals of
medicine is misguided and risks inconsistency,
even if
we adopt a social
constructivist approach.
Moreover, there is a problem with the normative assumptions behind the claim that
medicalization going beyond the ‘proper goals’ of medicine is wrong. To say that
the problem or cause of harm is commonplace provides little indication that we
should not address it. It might have been commonplace for humans to get cold, yet
we build houses and install heating systems; it might have been usual for people to
die before 30, yet we welcome the chance to live longer if the quality of life is
acceptable; it might have been usual for people to die of polio, yet we welcome the
eradication of the disease and associated suffering (Harris, 2007) – the fact that an
evil is usual, does not take away the permissibility of attempts to avert it, nor does
the fact that a benefit is unusual make it morally impermissible to seek it.
Even if
we accept that commonplace problems should not be medicalized, this says nothing
about the permissibility of addressing them. But
if we want to address them, why
not do it via medical means when those means are available and effective? In this
context, Harris (2007) proposed that we extend the notion of the proper goals of
medicine to making people better, broadly conceived. This may include ‘making us
better than well’ and giving us what we desire insofar as this is compatible with
morality, is lawful, and so on.
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: