FIGURE 3.1
Persepolis. The highly integrated hierarchy (dignitaries, the king’s guard,
tributaries carrying gifts) of the ancient Persian empire as represented on
the walls of Persepolis (near Shiraz, Iran), built in the sixth century BCE
and burnt down by Alexander the Great in BCE 330.
50 How politics works
• is meaningful within the framework of the community’s cultural and social
values; in other words, they must fail if they are drafted at the drawing board
and then imposed over the participants – as it often happened in colonial times.
Here also lies a problem, though not an insurmountable difficulty in the legis-
lating activity of a post-national quasi-polity like the European Union.
It is now clear that the institutions we are talking about are both formal, or legal,
and informal. The former prevail in domestic politics, since states all around the
world have adopted the Western tendency to juridify all existing rules, except
those that cannot be made explicit or public for reasons of decency or hypocrisy.
Between states ‘international regimes’ (see Chapter 6) can be regarded as informal
or semi-formal institutions.
Institutions are a key concept in jurisprudence and sociology, why not also in
political philosophy? They play indeed a role in shaping the actors’ behaviour in as
much as they
•
define their roles, that is
•
the motivations and interests that are possible within the given but also ever-
changing framework of shared rules, and
• give information over my and the others’ expectations and the negative and
positive incentives that can be brought to bear.
In a word, institutions shape the universe of meanings actors put in their own
actions and recognise in the behaviour of others. They sustain a grid of interaction
that is at the core of politics, of which they are along with power structures and
decision making the key component. Politics is a power-decision-institution trinity or
triangle. For actions or processes that lie outside this realm, the use of the adjective
‘political’ (calling, for example, the writing of a song or the wearing of a piece of
cloth, a political action) seems to be misplaced and inflationary – if we agree on
using words in a binding and substantial way.
* * *
We cannot leave the explanation of order and institution without looking into an
element we have so far barely mentioned: fear. In different versions, fear is a prem-
ise, a component, but also a product of politics. Fear is an emotion or, as writers of
politics used to say, a passion;
2
passions are elements of politics whose dynamics are
different from, say, that of interest or obligation.
Fear is a premise of politics in the contractarian account of it: it is the fear of
being killed, maimed and robbed by others in the state of nature that drives human
beings, as we shall soon see, to seek respite and protection under the powerful claws
of Leviathan; in the state of civility the natural and limitless fear of death and ruin is
replaced by the fear of law (metus legis, in Hobbes’s Latin) and punishment, a pillar
of peace and security.
Order, institutions, models 51
Regardless of contract theory, we know fear to be present in a multifaceted way
in our communal life: fear of war, terrorism, fear of losing one’s job and savings, fear
of authoritarian developments in some countries, fear of losing the election along
with one’s own status, but also fear of foreigners and immigrants. Fear is not like
fear: we need a distinction. Fear can be a protective sentinel against real dangers
that threaten our community, be it our town (in the case of an increased crime or
unemployment wave) or humankind (in the case of a looming nuclear war). With-
out this reasonable fear, communities would be at risk, and would not prepare for
lasting protection against, say, floods or cyber attacks. Let us call it realistic fear as to
keep it from the neurotic fear that projects our inner sense of insecurity or panic into
the faces of people with a different skin colour.
3
The history of intolerance, rac-
ism and fascist movements is full of currents of neurotic fear, which, spontaneous
or artificially fostered, is crucial to the build-up of pathological political identities
(wall-identities, as we have seen in the last chapter). In a way, politics consists of rec-
ognising what is reasonably worth being feared, while at the same time dismissing
all incitements to fear as an instrument of bellicose and irrational mass mobilisation.
Without skillfully managing fear in its twin face, a political regime can hardly sta-
bilise itself and gain legitimation with the ruled.
Postmodernists believe no distinction makes sense and that fear is just a subjec-
tive, illogical feature, to which no reality check is relevant. This belief is similar to
the refusal, mentioned in Chapter 2, to keep symbol apart from myth, thus main-
taining that all foundation narrative cannot but be mythical. This is all far from real
politics, in which those distinctions are held valid and broadly used by actors. In
particular, there are two criteria for keeping realistic and reasonable fear separate
from the neurotic one: first, in a world shaped by technology, comes the check by
science and scientific institutions, which can clarify questions, such as uncertainty
about Genetically Modified Organisms or the so-far insufficient preoccupation
with global warming. To make good use of scientific knowledge, however, a society
has to be capable of open and free public debate, in which instances of the two
fears are debated and citizens can develop an informed opinion. Though this does
not happen in democracies alone, it happens at best in a democratic framework; the
postmodernist enthusiasm for the blurring of distinctions witnesses, among other
things, a disbelief in the ability of liberal-democratic procedures to have a better
relationship to the truth than other regimes. This is now endangered by the non-
chalant relationship to the truth, in particular the scientific truth, shown by a new
generation of populist demagogues, but also by the citizens attracted by the false
claims, bizarre myths and emotionally overloaded beliefs that abound on the web.
The existence of neurotic fear – as well as the use made of it by fear-mongers
and charlatans in order to bring confusion among the public and make them prone
to populist and dictatorial leaders – has misled some authors to see only this side
of the coin and to try to expel fear from (civilised, democratic) politics altogether.
This is neither possible nor convenient because of the counter-intentional effects
that come with the cancellation of an element of reality; a theoretically balanced
and differentiated approach promises a better regulation of fear.
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |