164 Ethics and politics
general; he believed that the equal exchange between
compensation and amount of
work provided by a single person, a principle characterising the first stage of commu-
nist society, would later make room for the formula ‘from each according to his ability,
to each according to his needs’ – thus establishing an equal procedure respecting and
promoting everybody’s individuality (Marx 1875).
In modern history, inequality worldwide went down from its previous peaks
after 1860 and particularly during the Great Depression of 1929, while gathering
again momentum after 1977 as a likely
side effect of globalisation, which can on the
other hand be credited for bringing down inequality among countries. The recent
and unmistakable growth of income inequality within countries as well as the dis-
appearance of any alternative economic model like the socialist one may stay in the
background of the growing philosophical attention on equality as an
ethical (rather
than political) guideline for course corrections inside capitalism. It could also be
asked if the arguments in favour of equality and redistribution, such as Rawls’s
(1999, §11) second principle of justice (difference principle), are not to be seen
as a
post-festum justification of the social policies launched
by the New Deal and
heavily under attack since the rise of neoliberalism with all its rhetoric in favour of
inequality as a path to wealth. As Hegel wrote in the Preface to his
Grundlinien der
Philosophie des Rechts/Elements of the Philosophy of Right, ‘When philosophy paints
its grey in grey, one form of life has become old, and by means of grey it cannot be
rejuvenated, but only known. The owl of Minerva [
scil. philosophy]
takes its flight
only when the shades of night are gathering’ (1821, 8).
* * *
Of all the major differentiations the concept under examination allows for, we
shall mention the following: substantive vs. procedural equality; equality of welfare/
equality of opportunities/equality of capabilities. The two sets of notions overlap
only partially.
Substantive equality places emphasis on the equality of the things that are a mat-
ter of redistribution, thus consisting of the possession of a nearly equal amount of
the goods that are regarded as relevant to the actor’s social condition. If it has to be
exactly the same number, Aristotle at the outset (1301)
3
of Book 5, Part 1 of
Politics
calls it
numeric equality in all things, as proposed – he adds – by democrats, while
their extreme counterpart, the oligarchs, vow for a likewise complete inequality.
Proportional equality means, on the contrary, to treat everybody according to a
same principle of fairness such as ‘treat like cases as like’ or ‘whatever the outcome
in
terms of goods, you will be treated not equally, but with equal respect for your
dignity and concerns’.
In the triad mentioned above, the great divide lies between
equality of welfare or
positions and the other two. In the former, the goal of society and government is
seen
as providing everybody, or rather every citizen, with the same degree of well-
being as based on a less and less unequal portion of material and relational goods.
In its roughest version this takes the form of the state’s monetary disbursements to
Liberty, equality and rights
165
the advantage of the worse-off. There is evidently a problem with the measurement
of welfare, which can be done either authoritatively from the top, at the risk of
infringing the individual’s autonomy, or referring
to preference satisfaction, which
creates a delicate problem of either allowing chaos or filtering preferences accord-
ing to a criterion almost impossible to reach by consensus.
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: