Overcoming The Obstacles
One of the central conceptual problems has been the tendency to reify the traditional behavioral categories despite the lack of evidence that children's behavior fits the categories. Thus, the most common hypotheses about the relationship between, for example, cognitive development and social development have assumed the validity of cognition and social skills as separate categories. This assumption is especially clear when cognitive development is postulated as a prerequisite for social development.
One such hypothesis that has received much attention involves the relation between cognition and morality: Cognitive development is hypothesized to be a prerequisite for moral development (see Kohlberg, 1969). In practice, this proposition has been taken to mean that performance on Piagetian tasks is a prerequisite for performance on Kohlberg's moral dilemmas. Why should conservation of amount of clay, for instance, be a prerequisite for moral reasoning based on normative concepts of good and bad (Kohlberg's stage 3)? Is there any sense in which conservation is included in the concepts of good and bad? Or is there any way that conservation is more fundamental to mental functioning than concepts of good and bad? Isn't it just as reasonable (or unreasonable) to suggest that concepts of good and bad may be a prerequisite for conservation? If evidence does not support the division of behavior into separate categories of cognition about science problems and moral reasoning, it cannot be meaningful to suggest that such cognition is a prerequisite for moral reasoning (Rest, 1979, 1983).
A similar problem arises when investigators assume that the behaviors captured by the traditional categories are totally separate, showing no relation to each other at all. One of the most neglected topics for school-age children is emotional development, which is sometimes treated as if it is not related at all to cognitive development. Perhaps this assumption helps explain why cognitive developmentalists have omitted emotions from their research agenda. In a later section we suggest some guidelines for stimulating the study of emotional development in school-age children, especially as it relates to cognitive development.
A third, related conceptual problem has been the assumption that one variable can capture an entire behavioral category. Self-esteem as assessed by a questionnaire is treated as measuring the core of the developing self (Hatter, 1983; Markus and Nurius, in this volume; Wylie, 1979). The stage of moral judgment, as assessed by reasoning about a set of moral dilemmas, is believed to assess the fundamental nature of moral development (Rest, 1983).
This mistaken assumption is at the heart of a recent controversy about the nature of brain-behavior relations. Several investigators have used measurements of the growth rate of children's heads as indexes of changes in the children's ability to learn (Epstein, 1978; Toepfer, 1979). Although no measures of learning were used, conclusions were drawn from the head-growth data about what children of different ages were able to learn. The relationship between brain growth and cognitive development is an exciting topic worthy of research, as we discuss later. It is important, however, that researchers differentiate what they are measuring from other developmental changes. Relationships between developments in different domains cannot be assumed; they must be assessed.
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: |