individual (with no aversion to risk) who tries to maximize his own
prospects, the classical doctrine is the ethic of perfect altruists. A surpris-
ing contrast indeed! By looking at these principles from the standpoint of
the original position, we see that a different complex of ideas underlies
them. Not only are they based upon contrary motivational assumptions,
but the notion of taking chances has a part in one view yet none in the
other. In the classical conception one chooses as if one will for certain
live through the experiences of each individual, seriatim as Lewis says,
and then sum up the result.
38
The idea of taking a chance on which person
one will turn out to be does not arise. Thus even if the concept of the
original position served no other purpose, it would be a useful analytic
device. Although the various principles of utility may often have similar
practical consequences, we can see that these conceptions derive from
markedly distinct assumptions.
There is, however, a peculiar feature of perfect altruism that deserves
mention. A perfect altruist can fulfill his desire only if someone else has
independent, or first-order, desires. To illustrate this fact, suppose that in
deciding what to do all vote to do what everyone else wants to do.
Obviously nothing gets settled; in fact, there is nothing to decide. For a
problem of justice to arise at least two persons must want to do something
other than whatever everyone else wants to do. It is impossible, then, to
assume that the parties are simply perfect altruists. They must have some
separate interests which may conflict. Justice as fairness models this
conflict by the assumption of mutual disinterest in the original position.
While this may prove to be an oversimplification, one can develop a
reasonably comprehensive conception of justice on this basis.
Some philosophers have accepted the utilitarian principle because they
believed that the idea of an impartial sympathetic spectator is the correct
interpretation of impartiality. Indeed, Hume thought that it offered the
only perspective from which moral judgments could be made coherent
and brought into line. Now moral judgments should be impartial; but
there is another way to achieve this. An impartial judgment, we can say, is
one rendered in accordance with the principles which would be chosen in
the original position. An impartial person is one whose situation and
character enable him to judge in accordance with these principles without
bias or prejudice. Instead of defining impartiality from the standpoint of a
sympathetic observer, we define impartiality from the standpoint of the
litigants themselves. It is they who must choose their conception of jus-
38. See
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: