principles in explaining the list would be a circular argument. We must
assume, then, that the list of primary goods can be accounted for by the
conception of goodness as rationality in conjunction with the general
facts about human wants and abilities, their characteristic phases and
requirements of nurture, the Aristotelian Principle, and the necessities of
social interdependence. At no point can we appeal to the constraints of
justice. But once we are satisfied that the list of primary goods can be
arrived at in this way, then in all further applications of the definition of
good the constraints of right may be freely invoked. I shall not argue the
case for the list of primary goods here, since their claims seem evident
enough. I shall, however, come back to this point from time to time,
especially in connection with the primary good of self-respect. In what
follows I take the list as established and apply the full theory of the good.
The test of this theory is that it should fit our considered judgments of
value in reflective equilibrium.
Two fundamental cases for the theory of the good remain to be consid-
ered. We must see whether the definition holds for both persons and
societies. In this section I discuss the case of persons, leaving the ques-
tion of a good society for the last chapter when all parts of justice as
fairness can be brought to bear. Now many philosophers have been will-
ing to accept some variant of goodness as rationality for artifacts and
roles, and for such nonmoral values as friendship and affection, the pur-
suit of knowledge and the enjoyment of beauty, and the like. Indeed, I
have emphasized that the main elements of goodness as rationality are
extremely common, being shared by philosophers of markedly different
persuasions. Nevertheless, it is often thought that this conception of the
good expresses an instrumental or economic theory of value that does not
hold for the case of moral worth. When we speak of the just or the
benevolent person as morally good, a different concept of goodness is
said to be involved.
23
I wish to argue, however, that once the principles of
right and justice are on hand, the full theory of goodness as rationality can
in fact cover these judgments. The reason why the so-called instrumental
or economic theory fails is that what is in effect the thin theory is applied
directly to the problem of moral worth. What we must do instead is to use
this theory only as a part of the description of the original position from
which the principles of right and justice are derived. We can then apply
the full theory of the good without restrictions and are free to use it for
23. See C. A. Campbell, “Moral and Non-Moral Values,”
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: