an assured prominence that provides sufficient grounds for choice. Of
course, it is conceivable that despite the unfortunate conditions under
which some of our desires and aversions have developed, they may still fit
into and even greatly enhance the fulfillment of rational plans. If so, they
turn out to be perfectly rational after all.
Finally, there are certain time-related principles that also can be used
to select among plans. The principle of postponement I have already
mentioned. It holds that, other things equal, rational plans try to keep our
hands free until we have a clear view of the relevant facts. And the
grounds for rejecting pure time preference we have also considered (§45).
We are to see our life as one whole, the activities of one rational subject
spread out in time. Mere temporal position, or distance from the present,
is not a reason for favoring one moment over another. Future aims may
not be discounted solely in virtue of being future, although we may, of
course, ascribe less weight to them if there are reasons for thinking that,
given their relation to other things, their fulfillment is less probable. The
intrinsic importance that we assign to different parts of our life should be
the same at every moment of time. These values should depend upon the
whole plan itself as far as we can determine it and should not be affected
by the contingencies of our present perspective.
Two other principles apply to the overall shape of plans through time.
One of these is that of continuity.
17
It reminds us that since a plan is a
scheduled sequence of activities, earlier and later activities are bound to
affect one another. The whole plan has a certain unity, a dominant theme.
There is not, so to speak, a separate utility function for each period. Not
only must effects between periods be taken into account, but substantial
swings up and down are presumably to be avoided. A second closely
related principle holds that we are to consider the advantages of rising, or
at least of not significantly declining, expectations. There are various
stages of life, each ideally with its own characteristic tasks and enjoy-
ments. Other things equal, we should arrange things at the earlier stages
so as to permit a happy life at the later ones. It would seem that for the
most part rising expectations over time are to be preferred. If the value of
an activity is assessed relative to its own period, assuming that this is
possible, we might try to explain this preference by the relatively greater
intensity of the pleasures of anticipation over those of memory. Even
though the total sum of enjoyment is the same when enjoyments are
17. This name is taken from Jan Tinbergen, “Optimum Savings and Utility Maximization over
Time,”
Do'stlaringiz bilan baham: